Gobierno de la ciudad de Buenos Aires
Hospital Neuropsiquiátrico
"Dr. José Tiburcio Borda"
Laboratorio de Investigaciones Electroneurobiológicas
y
Revista
Electroneurobiología
ISSN: ONLINE 1850-1826 - PRINT 0328-0446
by
Stefan Schweizer
Landhausstraße 153, 70188 Stuttgart
stef.schweizer[at]gmx.de
Electroneurobiología 2007; 15 (4), pp. 63-95; URL http://electroneubio.secyt.gov.ar/index2.htm
Copyright
© September 2007 Electroneurobiología. Diese Forschungsarbeit ist
öffentlich zugänglich. Die treue Reproduktion und die Verbreitung durch Medien
ist nur unter folgenden Bedingungen gestattet: Wiedergabe dieses Absatzes sowie
Angabe der kompletten Referenz bei Veröffentlichung, inklusive der originalen
Internetadresse (URL, siehe oben). / Este texto es un artículo de acceso público; su copia exacta y redistribución
por cualquier medio están permitidas bajo la condición de conservar esta
noticia y la referencia completa a su publicación incluyendo la URL (ver
arriba). / This is an Open Access article: verbatim copying and redistribution
of this article are permitted in all media for any purpose, provided this
notice is preserved along with the article's full citation and URL (above).
Accepted: 21 September 2007
Printing this .html file does not
keep page numbers or formats. You can download a .PDF (recommended: 650
kB) or .DOC (440 kB) file for reading or printing, either from here or from / Puede obtener un archivo .PDF (recomendado: 650 kB) o bien .DOC (440 kB) para
leer o imprimir este artículo, desde aquí o de http://electroneubio.secyt.gov.ar/index2.htm
ABSTRACT: This essay starts with the thesis that major
parts of constructivist theory have found a cozy dwelling in contemporary
pedagogical-didactical discourse. Recent policy reforms in the German education
sector are an example thereof. Nevertheless, theories of constructivism are not
always apparent as such. Too often, when an author openly refers to constructivism
his or her ideas are dismissed. This owes to the fact that, in general, history
of science and theory of science have not yet thought over constructivism and
autopoiesis deeply enough. A further problem is that the radicalism of constructivism
often evokes the idea of arbitrariness.
The present essay tries to fill this gap in scientific discourse. It
also contributes to the scientific, historical-genetic systematisation of
paradigms. As the theoretical source of constructivist theory, German Idealism
– for example, the works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte and Friedrich W. J.
Schelling – is identified. Schmidt and von Glasersfeld later on contributed
further specifications. Still older roots, digging in Aristotelean notions, have
been pointed out by Mario Crocco and Colin Dougall for the theory of
autopoiesis composed by neurobiologists Maturana and Varela, who were born in a
culture partly shaped by four centuries of Aristotelean, Jesuit schooling; thus
far, however, the present writer has not yet carried his research program onto the
study of such roots. Autopoiesis theory, which basically dovetails and
complements the constructivist paradigm, illustrates the implications of a
theory of science as regards the theory of self-organisation.
After these steps of fundamental scientific reflection, it is possible
to discuss and assess the merits of a pedagogy and a didactics inspired by
constructivism: in the arrived-to scenario, the outcome of a constructivist
pedagogy can be systematically derived from the theoretical framework. Many consequences
of constructivism are nowadays widespread in the academic community concerned
with pedagogy and didactics. The main feature of constructivist pedagogy and
didactics is the focus on the student. Students are considered autopoietically
closed systems and structural-selective acting systems that are only able to
act on their own motivation and are incapable to respond to external motives.
Therefore self-study, partner- or groupwork is viewed as the ideal means of
successful education.
·
ZUSAMMENFASSUNG: Dieser Aufsatz beginnt mit
der These, dass wesentliche Teile der konstruktivistischen Theorie im
zeitgenössischen pädagogisch-didaktischen Diskurs implizit fest verankert sind.
Neuere politische Reformen im deutschen Erziehungsbereich stellen dafür ein Beispiel
dar. Nichtsdestoweniger sind Theorien des Konstruktivismus nicht immer offensichtlich
als solche gekennzeichnet. Auch wird oft, wenn sich ein/e Autor/in auf den
Konstruktivismus bezieht, von seinen oder ihren Ideen Abschied genommen. Dies
beruht auf der Tatsache, dass im Allgemeinen die Geschichte und Theorie der
Wissenschaft noch nicht genug über die wissenschaftshistorische und
–theoretische Fundierung des Konstruktivismus und der Autopoiese reflektiert
hat. Ein weiteres Problem besteht darin, dass der Radikalismus des Konstruktivismus
oft die Idee der Willkürlichkeit hervorruft.
Der
gegenwärtige Aufsatz versucht diese Lücken im wissenschaftlichen Diskurs zu
schließen. Er trägt auch zu der wissenschaftlichen, geschichtlich begründeten
Systematisierung von Paradigmen bei. Als die theoretische Quelle der
konstruktivistischen Theorie wird Deutscher Idealismus – zum Beispiel die Werke
von Johann Gottlieb Fichte und Friedrich W. J. Schelling – bestimmt. Schmidt
und von Glasersfeld trugen später weitere Entwürfe bei. Auf noch ältere
Wurzeln, die in Ansichten von Aristoteles graben, wurde von Mario Crocco and
Colin Dougall auf die Theorie der Autopoiesie hingewiesen, die von den Neurobiologen
Maturana und Varela aufgestellt wurde. Diese wurden in einer Kultur geboren,
die durch vier Jahrhunderte aristotelischer und jesuitischer Schulung geprägt
war. So weit auf das Studium solcher Wurzeln hat der gegenwärtige Schreiber
sein Forschungs-Programm jedoch noch nicht fortgesetzt. Die Theorie der
Autopoiesie, welche hauptsächlich das konstruktivistische Paradigma koordiniert
und ergänzt, illustriert die Auswirkungen einer Wissenschaftstheorie v.a. in
Anbetracht der Theorie der Selbst-Organisation.
Nach diesen Schritten grundlegender
wissenschaftlicher Reflexion ist es möglich, die Verdienste einer durch den
Konstruktivismus inspirierten Pädagogik und Didaktik zu diskutieren und
einzuschätzen: Im Szenario des Angekommen-Seins, kann das Ergebnis einer
konstruktivistischen Pädagogik systematisch vom theoretischen Rahmenwerk
abgeleitet werden. Viele Folgen des Konstruktivismus sind heutzutage weit verbreitet
in der akademischen Gesellschaft, die sich mit Pädagogik und Didaktik befasst.
Das Hauptmerkmal konstruktivistischer Pädagogik und Didaktik ist das Augenmerk
auf den Schüler und Studenten. Autopoietisch geschlossene und strukturselektiv
agierende Systeme sind nur zum Agieren fähig. Deshalb gilt z.B. Gruppenarbeit
heute als probates Mittel für den schulischen Unterricht.
·
RESUMEN: Este trabajo comienza por la
tesis de que grandes porciones de la teoría constructivista hallaron cálida
acogida en el discurso pedagógico-didáctico contemporáneo. Son ejemplo de ello
las recientes reformas en las políticas públicas del sector educación en
Alemania. Pero las teorías constructivistas no siempre se distinguen fácilmente
como tales, tal vez porque a menudo, cuando un autor se refiere abiertamente al
constructivismo, sus ideas son rebajadas. Se debe esto a que, en general, la
historia de la ciencia y la teoría de la ciencia todavía no han pensado con
suficiente profundidad el constructivismo y la autopoiesis. Otra dificultad que
se añade consiste en que la radicalidad del constructivismo con frecuencia
evoca la idea de arbitrariedad.
El presente ensayo trata de cubrir ese hueco del discurso científico y
contribuir a la sistematización científica, histórico-genética, de paradigmas
nocionales. Como raíz y fuente ideológica de la teoría constructivista se
identifica al idealismo alemán; por ejemplo, la obra de Johann Gottlieb Fichte
y Friedrich W. J. Schelling; más tarde, Schmidt y von Glasersfeld aportarían
mayores especificaciones. Raíces aún más antiguas, arraigadas en conceptos de Aristotéles,
han sido señaladas por Mario Crocco y Colin Dougall para la teoría de la
autopoiesis compuesta por los neurobiólogos Maturana y Varela, nacidos en una
cultura en gran parte moldeada por cuatro siglos de enseñanza aristotélica
jesuítica; el presente autor, empero, hasta ahora no ha extendido su programa
de investigación hasta el estudio de esas raíces. La teoría de la autopoiesis,
que entronca, articula y complementa el paradigma constructivista, ilustra las
implicaciones de una teoría de la ciencia sobre la teoría de la auto-organización.
Tras esas etapas de reflexión científica, de carácter fundamental, se
hace posible analizar y evaluar los méritos de una pedagogía y una didáctica
inspiradas en el constructivismo. En efecto, desde tal perspectiva, las consecuencias
de la pedagogía constructivista pueden deducirse sistemáticamente del marco
teórico. En nuestros días muchas secuelas del constructivismo se expandieron
ampliamente a través de la comunidad académica vinculada a la pedagogía y didáctica.
El rasgo prominente de la pedagogía y didáctica constructivistas es el foco que
pone en el estudiante. Los estudiantes son considerados sistemas autopoieticamente
cerrados y sistemas que obran de modo estructural-selectivo, sólo capaces de
actuar en base a su propia ocurrencia e incapaces de responder a las incitaciones
externas. Por ello el medio ideal de la educación exitosa es visto en la autoinstrucción
y el trabajo en grupo o entre asociados.
1. Introduction
The author has already pointed out that a
reflection in History of Science, about the philosophical and paradigmatic background
of self-organisation theories, reveals that German idealism – mainly, Fichte's
ideas – generated the modern self-organisation-theories and, on the way, the
constructivism, which derives from it.[1]
This essay builds on this fundamental insight, also expounded elsewhere[2],
and asks here after its consequences in the area of pedagogy and the didactic
disciplines. As regards the discussion details, the present exposition follows
a middle course since, for the said purpose, the analysis of the conceptual
historical grounds of modern constructivist pedagogy can no longer be carried
out so elaborately as it was previously done. Nevertheless, it is necessary to
illustrate at least the essential part of that argumentative reasoning, before
bringing in the effects on the constructivist pedagogy and didactic.
At
constructivism, an interdisciplinary paradigm is dealt with. The following
disciplines, inter alia, make use of
theories from the constructivistic stock:
v
Biology
v
Philosophy
v
Political Science
v
Sociology
v
Discourse Analysis
v
Literary Studies
v
Systems Theory
v
Chemistry
v
Physics
v
Medicine
v
Neurophysiology
This enumeration
claims no completeness and, as a further discipline, pedagogy has to be named.
In pedagogy the constructivist body of thought finds multiple uses. Essential
parts of the spreading reforms in education and education planning are based on
the constructivist body of thought. The student is to gain competences, rather
than acquiring cognoscitive curricular contents forwarded by the teacher; or,
in other words, improvement in learning primarily represent improvements in
competences.[3]
Constructivist approaches are also found in the control of the educative system:
schools get a higher level of autonomy. Any efforts toward controlling,
specially those by the Ministry or other administrative bodies, can be no more
than controlling the progress of self-controlling.
As it also occurs in other disciplines,
the scepticism regarding constructivist theories is nevertheless extensive.[4]
This results, inter alia, from the
uninhibitedness and radicalism of the constructivist body of thought. Who embraces
the cause of constructivism in most cases only communicates its conclusions. The
historical correlations relating to concepts and problems become concealed, a suppression
not seldom due, in point of fact, just to plain unawareness. The historical dimensions
of science are rarely found in the pedagogical literature, and any diachronic
overviews use to be – at most – just short descriptive notes.
As this article wishes being of help to
moderate these limitations, it starts with a discussion in the context of history
of science and history of ideas, in which German idealism is identified as the precursor
of the constructivist body of thought. Then, as the system-theoretical biological
model of autopoiesis, by Chilean neurobiologists Maturana and Varela, lends
itself finely to science-theoretical reflections, this feature is tapped for
presenting autopoiesis in regard to its numerous discursive applications. After
that, so as to bring the present article to a close, the constructivist-pedagogical
body of thought is plainly and most succinctly represented, undiscussed but
with explicit references to the previous exposition. The expected upshot is
that no longer the thus presented results of constructivist pedagogy and
didactics might appear surprising, or even mind-boggling.
2. A reflection in history of science: idealism as the philosophical grounding of autopoiesis
The philosophical roots of radical
constructivism and the "theory of autopoiesis" are to be looked for
in German idealism, especially in Kant, Fichte, and Schelling. There the roots
of the constructivist pedagogical discourse lie.
2.1 Kant's Copernican
turn of transcendental philosophy
Kant’s philosophy runs under the
label of Critical Idealism and functions as a precursor of German Idealism. Critical
idealism subjects to a fundamental examination the cognitive processes going on
in the cognizing subject. That means, Kant does not let the philosophical reason
wander over the unknown quarters of our material world. He rather concentrates
the attention on the mind's inner space.[5]
Besides, the similarity of the secularist trends in idealism and autopoiesis
has to be pointed out, too: both try to acquire an advanced explanatory power
without taking resource of transcendental constructions.[6] In
this very fashion Kant attempts to enlighten, by means of the (pure) mind, the
things behind the perceptible.[7]
The interest of Kant’s reasoning decant into three questions:
-
what one could know (was man wissen könne)
-
what one should do (was man tun solle), and
-
what one is allowed to hope (was man hoffen dürfe).
Of these
questions, the first one is speculative, the second practical, the third at once
practical as well as theoretical[8].
In addition, one can make reference to Kant’s transcendental physics as a
metaphysics of the meta-physics. And for Kant, meta-physics is the scientific
cognition, when it is compelled to jump, by way of concepts, beyond the empirical
experience. This comes to be the case as it pronouces itself about knowledge,
about the world – or reality – in general; about morality, beauty, or history.[9]
There the intellect draws up a picture of the world that appears, to it, as the
actual reality, in the sense of what is objectively given. This activity of the
subject brings about, as its result, the creation (of the world): "For we
do not know nature but as the totality of appearances, i.e., of representations in us, and hence we can only derive the
laws of its connexion from the principles of their connexion in us, that is
from the conditions of their necessary union in consciousness, which
constitutes the possibility of experience." [10] In his critique of the pure reason, Kant thus lays
the foundations of an epistemological change of paradigm, by essaying to prove
that we are not cognizant of the world as it is, but of the world as it seems
to be so: simply as we recognize it. The recognizing mind is not an impression
of the world, but the world is an impression of human mind.[11]
Experience thus cannot be the showing itself, in our sensory intuition, of an essence
existing independently of us, "but the conceptual and subjective schematizing
of a spatial-temporal givenness." [12] It is the „pure sensory view as space and time"
that "which makes the cognizance a
priori possible, and this no more than for sensory realities." [13] Here the parallelism with the autopoiesis theory's
cognitive autonomy is to become evident. It should be noted that, in this
context, the sources of metaphysical knowledge can neither be of empirical
origin, nor deduced from experiments.[14]
So the subject
brings up, i.e. suscitates, the world.
Whence it comes that this world is perceived in correspondence with the subject's
structure, and only can be acted upon along with it. This corresponds to the
autopoietical features of "structure
determination" and "operational
unity". [15] It ought to be critically protested, in this regard, that
for Kant subjective cognition is not identical with a not-objective cognition,
as the consciousness of each and every human being is structured in a way more
or less similar. For that reason, the subjective cognition's meanings can be
intersubjectively extrapolated, and shared. Therefore a distinction regarding
the premises of the autopoiesis theory takes place, since in autopoiesis theory
the living beings' organisation is identical but their structure is different.[16]
This discrepancy is cleared up in Fichte. Kant asserts that the function of
thinking turns up from an activity whose originator is the self-conscious
subject. That is to say, the intellect draws up a world picture in a sovereign
way. Facts arise from the activity of the subjectivity, in such a way that one
can say that facts would be our creation.[17]
It further is specified that there is a relationship between the object's
structure and the attendant form of judgement; or, that what we call "objects"
is nothing else but "that, whereupon we, with our accurate judgements, make reference to."."[18]
In the vein of Aristotle's Prime Mover, which moves toward Itself (thereby
shaping up the whole Nature, with its admirably harmonized motions) every other
thing "autonomously", by way of the love for It that the very Prime
Mover by itself inspires in every other thing's heart, likewise in Kant the
appeal of the real things in themselves acts as raw matter on the spirit's
cognitive power and a priori forms,
and is shaped up by these. A priori
means a possibility of universal application, as well as a transcendental stage
– or plane – of sensory perception.[19]
The acquisition of knowledge in this manner is a composite occurrence. It does
not only consist in the cognitive apprehension of sensual impressions. Kant's
articulation of rational and empirical components in the occurrence of each
acquisition of knowledge concurs with the basic views of the "theory of autopoiesis",
as both components, i.e. the own understanding
as ratio and the world as empirical fact, are created by the own self.
2.2 Fichte’s
constituting of the world by the subject
In current
discussions, Kant is appreciated as a theorist of science. Nevertheless, it is
reserved to Fichte (in contradistinction to Kant) the distinguishing trait of
having put "the main emphasis, of the scientific acquisition of knowledge,
on the deductive method" [20]. Whence Fichte demands that philosophy be established
on some absolute, self-evident proposition, from which everything else could be
deduced.[21]
More emphatically even than Kant, Fichte puts the subject into the focal point.
Is the human being free and independent, or only a product or manifestation of
an alien force? [22] Fichte’s philosophical system can be understood as a
praxis or system of action. The ego is identical to willing and knowing.[23]
All heteronomy of the subject is denied, and it is highlighted the subject's
own endeavour to encompass the prevailing infinity.[24]
Fichte radicalizes Kant, as he rails against the doctrine of the
"dogmatism" – until then ruling – whereby the human is the product of
outer things and relationships. Fichte thinks: „I and my world are the product
of my free activity" [25]
He made the import of the spirit stronger, as "it produces a world out of
the nothing, because only the I of the spirit exists" [26].
This yields an exact correspondence with the premises of the autopoiesis'
axioms of cognitive autonomy, structural determination, and operational unity. In
that connection these characteristic features can be clarified, and more
concretely formulated, as that the subject brings up the world (as object), and
the consistence of the object is totally dependent of the distinctively
characterized, structured activity of the subject.
If the
consciousness considers itself, and reflects on the preconditions of the own
possibilities, it discovers the own ‘I’-condition or ego-hood (thesis), which is thinkable only in connection
with a ‘Non-I’ (antithesis, as this
that the world can become). Both steps are themselves carried out
subject-immanently, i.e. inside of
the subject, thus coming along to abolish the contradiction, into the unity of
the higher ego (synthesis). This is
also the Absolute Ego.[27]
One may not equate the Absolute Ego with the individual, because it is the
individual who has to be deduced from the Absolute Ego.[28]
This Fichte pointedly formulates, by declaring that the (dividable) Ego sets up
itself, which again sets up, against itself, a dividable non-Ego: „The striving
of the I can't be set without setting a counter-striving by the non-I; for, the
striving of the first comes from causality, but hasn’t causality; and that it
hasn’t got any causality, is why it hasn’t got its foundation from itself, because
otherwise the same striving wouldn’t be a striving, but nothing." [29] The subject's setting and countersetting work flows
into a (dialectical) synthesis of subject and object as Ego and Non-Ego,
whereby both the knowledge owned by the Ego, as well as its reflection, consist
of a permanent setting-countersetting dialectic.[30]
I can be concluded that the spirit has to be interpreted as act, specifically
as an act that although determined a
priori constitutes everything real,
i.e. the nature etc., as knowledge. The Being, as the Whole of the
self-realising possibilities in its self-excitation, is not material. It rather
grants spirit, and comes into ex-sistence as the manifestation in consciousness
of the multiplicity of its possibilities. The consciousness of the Being is the
form, whereby the Being comes to ex-sistence and brings up for itself its
possibilities, of phenomenizing as the multiplicity of an appearance-world and
of placing its capacity of becoming conscious into its own view and knowledge.[31]
In the autopoiesis-theory, the systems are self-organizing and self-producing. Thereby
the system-immanent existence, and its relation to objects, are produced. Fichte
names this a self-excitation of the spirit (Selbsterregung
des Geistes), active to produce the world. The consequence is the same, as
in both cases the external objects get constituted by the subject's activity. The
requisites of the autopoiesis axioms of structural determination and
operational closure are satisfied in Fichte’s philosophy. About the objective
existence of objects (Non-I realities), only statements after the subject's
structure can be made. These reflections exactly correspond with the positions
of the radical constructivism. Reality is created by the powers of imagination.[32] Cognition is self-set, in Fichte; the
subject can act, can never react. Reality's composition is moulded in the
subject's structure.
.
Aristotle
(384-322 b.C), two Roman copies (mantle is a modern addition) of a lost bronze
portrait made by Lysippos around 330 BC
Two portraits of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
Left, Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814). Right, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph
Schelling,
Ritter von Schelling (1775-1854), young and old.
2.3 Friedrich Schelling's subject-object
theory
The development, from Fichte’s
philosophy of consciousnes to Schelling’s philosophy of nature, is supported on
methodological grounds.[33] The early Schelling says that the ego is world-creator.
Nature appears as a symbol of the spirit, which reflects himself in the exterior.[34]
So in Schelling the perspective changes, as the interrogation comes to ask for
how nature can become an object for the creator subject's gaze. Schelling puts
it in this way: nature can become object for the cognizing subject, as it is
the product of an unconsciously acting subject; a product that, in its most
basic structure, harmonises with the structure of the ego.[35]
Thus also Schelling sees how the subject builds up the object, but in
Schelling's view this object has its own right as a real object, independent of
the subject. The dialectic game of subject and object has to be regarded as foundation
of the understanding of reality: "Every and any knowledge is based on the
agreement of an objective with a subjective" [36].
On the other hand, the object presses onto the subject, as it, inasmuch as
foreign to consciousness, presses for becoming conscious. This constitution of
reality comes out of a conflict that has several levels: "So much for sure
as it is that all knowledge in general is based on that contrast of
intelligence and object, so surely that contrast cannot rise without object...
Intelligence can never expand itself into infinity, prevented as it is from
doing this by its own striving for coming back into itself. But, just as little
it can totally come back into itself, prevented as it is from doing this by the
trend toward being itself infinity." [37]
Inasmuch as nature, consciousness has to be seen as a reflection of the spirit.
By way of the abundance and wealth of nature, its objectivity and thereby its
difference to the ego is demonstrated.
Nature has to be
regarded as life and soul; it represents a way to the spirit, a way whereby the
spirit can find nature. Nature is in a permanently living and active process,
and has to be conceived of as a living unity: "It is an infinite productive
organism" („Sie ist ein unendlich
produktiver Organismus") [38].
Thereby the identity of nature and spirit – that characterizes Schelling’s Philosophy of Identity – comes to light.
Subject is object, reality is ideality. Nature is visible spirit, spirit is invisible
nature. The many coincides with the One, the Absolute.[39]
An essential characterization, of the ego as subject and object, results
straight off.[40]
Later – it might be worth a mention – Schelling’s anthropologized philosophy of
identity runs on the woman. This one is an object that pushes her own way to
get in front of the subject, the male, for his watching. In a microcosmical
analogy, the combination of the absolute and the omnicomprehensive takes place
at an ideal combination of the types of man and woman; thus, of subject and
object.
With Schelling,
the removal of spiritual fatherhood for the "theory of autopoiesis"
intensifies. Still, references pointing out to the premises of the autopoiesis
theory can be produced while, at the same time, noncommensurable components exist.
Schelling demands
a higher knowledge, one that could become investigated by the speculative
philosophy of nature.[41]
In Schelling's philosophy, Michaela Boenke spots evident parallels with the modern
self-organisation discourse. Thus she properly refuses revolutionary radicality
to this paradigm of modern science: at self-organisation it is dealt with "the
science of organisations, or systems, that organize themselves, this explaining
how, by means of elementary interactions, order comes into being and is
maintained. Similar to Schelling, nature and cognition are comprehended as
self-organizing systems" [42].
In the autopoiesis' discourse, experience can only be explained by the functioning
mechanisms of the brain.
2.4 Radical
constructivism and the "theory of autopoiesis"
Until our times, the relationships
of German Idealism and the system-theoretical biological theory of autopoiesis
of Maturana and Varela had remained chiefly in the dark.[43]
In contrast, the connections between radical constructivism and theory of
autopoiesis are well known. The very Maturana and Varela, in their writings,
make reference to ideas and views of radical constructivism, e. g. in the versions of Ernst von Glasersfeld
and Sigfried Schmidt. Systems can act and never react, and this affords the
epistemological grounds: „Reality is consequently the territory of objects and,
thus, it is that which can be delimited as real. Therefore there is no doubt
about this, i.e. about what reality
is: to wit, an area that is determined by the operations of the observer."[44]
So one comes to the philosophical-epistemological position of radical constructivism,
a position „that, by continuing sceptical and constitutive theoretical reflections,
conceives each form of cognition – even the cognizer itself – as a construction
of an observer. Recognizing does not mean the passive figuration of an external
objective reality, but denotes a process of original production, i.e. the construction of a cognitive
world. The real world itself is no experienceable reality; reality is rather an
always agreed to, observed, invented, therefore constructed reality" [45].
Glasersfeld asks,
What radical constructivism is? His answer is: „Simply expressed, it deals with
an unconventional way to look at the problems of knowledge and cognition.
Radical constructivism is based on the assumption, that every knowledge …
exists only in the heads of humans and that the thinking subject can construct
his knowledge only on the basis of the own experience. What we construct out of
our experience, this alone, forms the world, in that we consciously live."
[46].
The radical constructivism is interpreted as a special approach of the
constructive theory of knowledge; it is about views of what is to be understood
by the term "reality". Nonetheless, this reality has not to be
equated with the being; such reality depends on knowledge [47], and reality is connected with the individuality or
subjectivity. His insisting, on the bondage of experience and knowledge to the
subject, leads v. Glasersfeld to a number of consequences.[48]
A marking attribute of radical constructivism[49]
is its abandoning the idea of any reality independent from subject.[50]
Consequently, theory of knowledge becomes a theory of knowledge acquisition. Absolutely,
social interaction is reality.[51]
Cognition serves the organisation of the subject’s world of experiences, not
the detection of a reality independent of the subject. Knowledge generates
itself depending on the subject, never being merely an object of passive
reception: "Knowledge is actively build up by the thinking subject" ("Wissen wird vom denkenden Subjekt aktiv
aufgebaut") [52].
Cognition is a mental instrument for adaptation, whose purpose consists in the
construction of viable[53]
conceptual structures. The advances in human knowledge can be characterized as
evolution, not as a movement drawing near to a truth. The function of "cognition
has an adaptive character, exactly in the biological sense of the word, and
aims at befitting or viability." [54].
A distinguishing
mark of radical constructivism is that the meaning of linguistic expressions is
evaluated as a result of individual experience. Thus, regarding communication,
meaning comes into being only from the partners of the communication and from
their effort to construct meanings in their cognition. With regard to the
learning, it is valid to say that the art of teaching has to consist in
building up the art of learning: „Constructivists… regard every knowledge as
instrumental. Thus reasons should be communicated to the learner at the start,
as to why certain ways of acting and thinking are regarded as desirable. From
that, necessarily, follows the explanation of the specific relations in which,
supposedly, the knowledge to be acquired is to function." [55]
The art of the teaching has little to do with the transfer of knowledge, "its
main aim ought to be to educate the art of learning" („ihr grundlegendes Ziel muß darin bestehen,
die Kunst des Lernens auszubilden.") [56]
All responsibility stays in the individual.
This point, in
the fields of history of ideas and philosophy, reminds again of the attitude of
idealism. A theory of knowledge oriented on the subject is synonymous with an
empirical theory of cognition, given that radical constructivism only can prove
itself truly instrumental at problem solving, via selection-like viability. Practical
survival decides about the usefulness of cognition and evolution.
Similarities to
Maturana’s evolutionary biological understanding of the term of progressive drift
are obvious. Based on this predisposition, the connection is to be pointed out
of the self-organisation discourse with newer scientific developments, e. g. inside of Anglo-American neurophysiology,
which claims that decision-making processes are organised in the brain by selforganisation
and networking.[57]
Terms like reality and truth only receive substandard meaning.[58]
3. Epistemological
considerations on the biological and system-theoretical conception of
autopoiesis
The axiomatic of the theory of autopoiesis
asserts that all living systems are by definition autopoietic systems, i.e. systems, and further
self-organizing ones. Life without external influences is conceivable. To draw
a contrast wih the vitalistic views still prevailing in the nineteenth century
in the historical-scientific context of the theory of autopoiesis, this notion
can be understood as a secularization or detranscendation of the life concept. Maturana
and Varela describe self-organization so: "Our suggestion is, that living
things characterize themselves in that they literally produce themselves all
the time. To this we make reference by calling their defining organisation an
'autopoietic organisation' " [59].
Whence it is sure that the living systems share the same organisation (or, form
of organisation): "By organisation
are to be understood the relations that must exist between the components of
something, so that it may be recognized as a member of certain class." [60]
Autopoietical organisation defines the unity of the system.[61]
The organisation is responsible for the production of itself. It is the same in
all living things, and constitutes the mentioned unity of these systems. In contrast,
those very systems differ from each other with regard to structure. It is in no
way amazing, therefore, that the difference between organisation and structure
be depicted as fundamental. The antagonist components, "invariance"
and "dynamics", come to play a role: "To me [...], the distinction
between organization and structure has been a fundamental distinction, namely
one that allowed us to tell apart what is invariant in a system and what is
allowed to change in it." [62]
The variable structure is called the constituent parts, the ones that constitute
in a concrete way a unit and realize its organization.[63]
The structure is variable: "The autopoiesis occurs as a dynamic process,
that cannot be comprehended by a static and momentary contemplation of its
constituent parts' distribution. That is why a living system exists only by
continuous structural transformations, demanded from its autopoiesis, and only
as long, as these transformations are retained in the constitution of their
ontogenesis [...] A living system can be realized in many different, changing,
dynamic structures." [64]
In contrast, the organisation of the living entity is constituting its identity
and is also invariant. Organisation and structure can be described as follows: "A
living thing is characterised by its autopoietical organisation. Different living
things differ by their different structures, but are not different with regard
to their organisation." [65]
A comparison of
autopoietical systems, as i.e. fish
and human beings are, shows that, in both cases, the comparison deals with
living systems. These, as regard to their autopoietical organisation and the
organisational closure related to it, are identical. Instead, with regard to
the structure, differences exist. In order to be able to exist autopoietically,
the fish need support by other medium,
i.e. an environment diverse of the one fit for human beings. The system-theoretical-cybernetic
"theory of autopoiesis" is specified by the following axioms; the
representation in eleven points serves for clearness:
1. Autopoietical
organisation exists at living systems and defines the system's unity. The organisation
of all autopoietical systems is identical; this organisation permits a
distinction vis-à-vis the environment. For living systems, it is valid to
affirm that, "Living systems as autopoietical systems are
structure-determined systems, and everything that is valid for structure-determined
systems is valid for them. That means, in particular, that everything that
happens in a living system, happens in the factual operation of the features
marking its constituent parts in accordance with their relations of neighbourhood
(relations of contiguity), which are produced just by this very operation. Thereby
the models of governance and regulation in no way reflect the factual
operations in the structural realization of a living system. They cannot do
this, just because they are not intertwined with the concrete relations of
contiguity." [66]
It is worth noting that the livings systems' autopoietical organisation has
implications on the systems' relations with the environment. The axiom makes possible
the delimitation of the autopoietical system from its environment, with which
the connections are verified in terms of relations of contiguity.
2. Constituent parts, and relations among
components, constitute autopoietical systems. The "theory of autopoiesis"
queries after the mode and form of the system's organisation. [67]
3. Among constituent parts, three sorts of
relationship exist, namely, the relations of constitution, specification, and
order. (1) The spatial extension of the system is produced by the relations of constitution. (2) The
identity of the system is established by the relations of specification. (3) The (autopoietical) process is
controlled by the relations of order.
4. The fourth axiom states that autopoietical
systems are organisationally closed, as their constituent parts produce relations
and the relations produce constituent parts. This is a circular causality, that
produces the system. The system organises itself, and thereby it produces itself.
Productions and renewals take place all the time within and during the
autopoietical process, as otherwise the system's very existence would become
endangered. In autopoietical systems, the character of circular organisation
guarantees the reception of the environmental support or environmental influences
– mainly allopoietical or originated in the medium – as it is necessary for the
system's existence, even if this support or those influences cannot be experienced
as such.
5. The autopoietical organisation moulds into
a concrete form the system's structure. This is dependent on allopoietical or environmental
support: e. g. air, as a medium for
breathing; other persons, as a necessity for development and plenitude of existence.
Therefore it is valid to assert: "Living systems are units of interaction.
They exist in a setting."[68]
The environments or media are allopoietical and autopoietical. Humans for
living need not only air (allopoietical), but humans. Both, in this sense, are
media.
6. Structural couplings take place between
autopoietical systems and their environmental supports. In this process a correspondence
is requisite: "A living system either exists as a dynamic, structurally
determinate system in structural coupling with the medium … or it doesn’t exist
at all. Or, in other words, a living system, as long as it lives and operates
in its area of existence, necessarily keeps a dynamic coincidence with its
milieu." [69]
If oxygen would not have been an environmental supportive means for human
beings, these, as they actually are, could not exist in the prevailing context.
7. As just seen, among autopoietical systems
and milieu structural couplings come to be, in whose structural complementarity
interactions take place. Structural couplings have effects able to change the
system states. This axiom refers just to the interactions among autopoietical
systems and milieux, namely to the special territory of structural couplings. Coevolution
means complementarity: "Interactions are achieved only as the environmental
medium and the system show structural complementarity. The biological term "coevolution"
clarifies complementary, recursive relations. The medium triggers actions of
the autopoietical system and these, in turn, cause other actions of the medium."[70]
8. The structure of autopoietic systems
determines the seven changes of state, just mentioned. This means, that the
outer influences make themselves represented at the system as perturbations. Thereby
autopoietic systems interpret the environment in a selective way, proper to
their structure. No changes in inner structure can be externally determined. Cognition
and autopoiesis are supposed identical; it is postulated that life is
cognition, and vice versa. The stimuli that are experienced are selfproduced. Everything
that stimulates the system into acting, has to be assessed in the system. A "structure-determined
system is a system, in which everything that happens, happens as structural
change…" As this assertion makes evident, autopoiesis theory takes for
granted the thorough inexistence of anything like empsyched systems, i.e. mixed structural-nonstructural systems,
whose organic regulation utilizes a diversity of non-structural intonative
reactions, called sensations. On the contrary, "This assertion means that
the structural changes of a structure-determined system in the wake of an interaction
cannot be determined from the outside. An external impulse, that interacts with
a structure-determined system, can only trigger in this system structural
changes, but these are determined by the system itself." [71]
In autopoietic systems, it is no question of distinguishing between inner and
outer influences. Influences are produced as system-immanent.
9. Territories for consensus rise into
existence, and become available, to the very extent that further autopoietic systems
stand in the same medium and permanent interactions develop among such systems.
Consensual areas come into being by structural couplings. It thereby seems,
from the observer perspective, that the two systems' changes of state reciprocally
determine each another, interactions thus coming into being. Yet the
autopoietic systems act.[72]
10. When, through the channel of the
linguistic modality, in the consensual areas, direct – i.e., first-order – practical coordinations between autopoietic
systems become also feasible, then a consensual area of second order arises. About
this phenomenon of linguistic communication, it is said: "Speech, as a
biological phenomenon, consists of a flow of ever recurring interactions, which
form a system of consensual behavioral coordinations of consensual behavioral
coordinations ... Whereby it comes to light that linguistic communication as a
process doesn’t take place in the body (nervous system) of the participants,
but in the said area of consensual behavioral coordinations, that manifests
itself in the flow of their recurrent bodily meetings." [73]
Language is thus not to be seen as immanent,
i.e. anchored to the system (nervous system), but as running in the autopoietic
systems' area of the consensual behavioral coordination. For the systems
installed in language, it is indeed possible to distinguish between "inside"
and "outside". It is contended that, by means of this area of linguistic
communication, human consciousness and human identity become generated. As
regards to human communication, the utilization of language is seen as significant:
"Humans operate as living systems in linguistic communication, i.e. in an area of recursive,
reciprocal consensual perturbative influences, that constitutes their territory
of existence as such. Therefore, as a territory of recursive consensual
coordination of actions, language is an area of existence, and as such, it is a
cognitive area: one, defined by the recursion of consensual distinctions in an
area of consensual distinctions."[74]
In this way, linguistic communication enables autopoietic systems for conscious
operation in an area of existence determined thereby. Agreeing with
Wittgenstein in freely formulating this concept, one could as well say this by
pointing out that the human beings' world is the world of their language.
11. By means of long lasting structural
couplings, the autopoietic systems of higher order can be built up. Important
is a distinction; namely, that an observer can describe as allopoietic the
coupled autopoietic systems in their relations, inasmuch as they had became constituent
units of a higher order system. This so happens, because in the coupling process
the systems that act as constituent parts fulfil a function for the higher
system, despite their actual being just in a system-supporting autopoietic
process. The process autonomy and the cognitive autonomy of autopoietic systems
are deduced from the theories of life and cognition. The first is featured by a
theory of dynamic systems, the second manifests itself in the cybernetics of
second order.[75]
Humberto Maturana Romecin (born
1928)
Francisco
Javier Varela García (1946-2001)
Ernst von Glasersfeld (born
1917)
4. Cognitive
Science, Interaction Psychology, and Empirical Pedagogy
Whence it results valid, for scientific theories and
scholastic knowledge, to maintain the opinion that a (nevertheless) transient
leader of German sociology, a vehement advocate of methodological individualism
and opponent of constructivism, admits: "Experiences inasmuch as theories
are nothing but constructions of the brain – or of the scientists' brains – at
first totally independent of an "objective" reality" anywise
characterized, then only along the inner processes and conditions of reproduction,
the autopoiesis, of the
self-construction of the brains and organisms that carry them" [76]
Along with it
goes the task of imagining a reality independent of the subject.[77]
The pedagogic discourse has adapted many ideas from the
constructivist-autopoietic discourse, above delineated.[78]
Sorry to say, and omitting no more than a few essays unfortunately rare to
find, among the authors of pedagogic literature only the fewest let the reader
see these relations.[79]
In addition, now essays exist that offer detailed analyses of constructivism as
a trend in the German didactic-pedagogic discourse too.[80]
Against the above outlined background, rather than surprise us, many of its
consequences nowadays resulting may explicate by themselves. And, what is more,
the stigma of being arbitrary and incomprehensible, occasionally sticked onto
the pedagogic-constructivist discourse, becomes invalid.
The so-called Situated Cognition is one of the
approaches feeding from the constructivist-autopoietic body of thought. This
approach emphasizes two features, none of which encounters like attention in
other learning and pedagogical theories. Situated Cognition focuses itself first
and foremost on the inclusion of the being situated of the learning. Thereby it
is concretely asked for, in which situation, and in which context, the learning
individually takes place, i.e. in
each of the learners. This aspect is completed by taking a higher-level perspective:
the social, cultural, and historical contexts have to be also looked upon in second
term. This certainly sounds banal, but its relevance almost cannot be
overestimated. From an eurocentrist perspective in the tradition of
Enlightenment, learning is frequently spoken of as an intrinsic value. It
follows that the permanent learning, unbroken along the entire life, owns a
value hard to outdo. But learning is contingent. The educational science "basically
can incorporate critically only those 'constructions', i.e. all myths and fragments of knowledge, which the pedagogy is
proud on" [81]
Moreover,
learning depends on conditions both sychronic and diachronic. One imagines the
learning underwent in a culture in which women's destiny is keeping house and
yard, giving birth to (male's) children, serving the man. Which value learning
has there, for women? Can one soundly speak of the value of learning, in an
African refugee camp? What about the school lessons in concentration camps? The
aforementioned points provide a certain guidance, appropriate for the discipline
of pedagogy. And one has to incorporate the topic of the physical-social
contexts of the thinker, into the issue of the cognitive events' being situated.
In the process, by "physical-social context", the "sphere"
of the student can be meant: does s/he grow up in a small communitarian
apartment? Is this communitarian apartment situated in a socially "weak"
milieu that features youth gangs, criminality, alcoholism, unemployment? With
whom does the student grow up? How do his social contacts look like? This
aspect, in addition, relates on the physical constitution of the individual: which
physical and psychological preconditions are given to start with? And, besides
the learner's being situated as regards the physical and social circumstances,
also the personal and social epistemologies play a role. This means that,
between the group and the individual, beliefs and concepts can differ. The formation
of these differences, as well as their becoming conscious, secure a learning
process for the individual as well as for the collective. With this, the interactive
relationships of individual and group becomes relevant to shape up the process
of learning.
A further point
is the so-called conceptual competence. This means, that individuals are able
to learn consciously. All of these three mentioned aspects require a partly
autonomic individual. And all of the three components prove to be even more
applicable in the assumption of an autopoietic individual. In the view under
consideration, every human, according to her or his structure and organisation,
is responsible for her or his own learning processes: "Accordingly the
subject (as living system) is the sole originator of the knowledge, its constitution
and construction. The human constructs his world, in which s/he lives
self-referentially and autopoietically." [82]
This didactic-pedagogic premise does not relieve the State, school, and
teachers from their responsibility to educate their autopoietically organised
students, or citizens. Rather they have to enable the students' learning
processes in their autopoietic frame.
The current
quintessence of pedagogy can therefore be summarized so: teachers don’t have to
transmit curricular contents, as they are instead responsible for the
organisation of learning processes. In this way, the transfer of the focus of
analysis onto the student has been outlined in the last reforms of the
educational plan in Europe. Autopoietic systems shape up their learning
processes by themselves. Mission and aim is, reaching to each pupil in her or
his autopoietic, selfreferential structure and organisation. Yet hardly one of
the reformers of the European educational plan or pedagogues imagines the
connections, in History of Ideas or History of Problems, of the constructivism
or the system-theoretical biological theory of autopoiesis with the German
Idealism. It is apparent that especially at this point, where the behaviorism
comes up against the borders, the constructivistic pedagogy has to get ahold.
With its initial
stimulus-response mechanism[83],
behaviorism has quickly reached the boundaries of the explanation in the
predicative, descriptive, and causal-analytical areas. The integration of the object
as a black box (stimulus ® organism ® response) has remedied, though just a little, this theoretical
insufficiency, or deficit. In this fissure, the constructivistic didactic
successfully places itself.
As regards the
constructivism's coming into being, an essential starting point was the problem
of coping with sluggish knowledge. In constructivist pedagogy, sluggish
knowledge typically means indirect, incoherent knowledge due to "frontal
schooling", which preclude experiencing an integrated connection. Frontal
schooling implies a teacher presenting input to the students by lecturing or by
dialectical means (teacher asks a question, gets an answer, asks another
question, and so on). In the search for alternatives, the network metaphor
comes into play, as it is used, for example, by neurophysiologists Singer and
Roth. Singer looks at the emergence of decision-making events assuming that it
occurs in the brain, as self-organized and network-organized processes.[84]
On the above outlined background, the outcomes encountered by the hard,
empirically orientated neurophysiology are not to surprise.
In the (radical-)
constructivist variant, it rather is indicated the relativity of such terms as reality, truth, etc.[85]
It is assumed that there are "just as many individual realities, as there
are real brains" ("ebensoviele individuelle Wirklichkeiten, wie
es reale Gehirne gibt") [86].
Each brain produces its own reality in accordance with its autopoietic and
self-referential organisation. Any processes of perception are self-organizing.[87]
The form of organisation is the same, namely autopoietic, but the structure of
the humans can vary.
This has taught
us the science-theoretical reflections of the system-theoretical-cybernetic
models of self-organisation. Along their lines, the constructivist pedagogy
tries to manage the mentioned issue, that of the sluggish knowledge.
In this endeavor,
it considers that when frontal schooling is being imparted to the students, the
external stimulation coming from the educator doesn’t reach – in the form of perturbations
– to these students, deemed autopoietic closed systems. So the teacher has
rather to organize also the circumstances and the set of parameters affecting
the pupil, so that the latter by herself or himself could enact her or his
learning in accordance with her or his structure and organisation. The
teacher's task, in the opinion of constructivist pedagogy, consists in building
up learning-arrangements, which offer to the pupils freedom to follow their own
ways of learning.[88]
A definitive goal
of the constructivist pedagogy is therefore raising the ability for transfer. In
this view, "ability for transfer" is the counterpart of "sluggish
knowledge".
On the background
of these succinct expositions, it has to be understood that the teacher should
not be the centre of the lessons. The teacher is rather the moderator of the
educational endeavors. On him it is incumbent to organize the lessons.
As steering
oneself is viewed as the central attribute of learning systems, one can ask,
whether and how possibly learning systems can be steered.[89]
Learning in constructivism is "constructive achievement of the individuals
[...], that can be prompted and accompanied by the teacher, but not steered. So
to the professional task of teachers it is incumbent to plan such learning's surroundings that allow
successful learning, and to accompany
this learning."[90]
Moreover, in this
context also it is valid that "If learning is understood as
„self-development of a cognitive system" (Aufschnaiter), the importance of
self-responsibility and active inner processing cannot be overstated." [91]
The old image of a foreign steering has to be revised. [92]
One rather has to replace foreign steering by reflexive self-steering.
Still, steering can therefore consist of
steering for self-steering. Otherwise the teacher would be superfluous. His or
her function can only consist in scheduling impulses. The impulse is the
initial ignition for the self-steering processes. From those theoretical
premises some conditions can be deduced, to be applied to the context of the
learning. The pedagogic-constructivist approach requires, for the learner, the
highest degrees of freedom that are possible. Only this degree of autonomy enables
the learner to become actively self–steering. Indispensable precondition is,
nevertheless, that the learner himself may recognize and appreciate the degrees
of freedom given and entrusted onto her or him. Accordingly, the profitable use
of the scope of action given to her or him is, so to speak, the learner's own
responsibility.
At this point,
some questions open up in connection with the psychology of the knowledge
acquisition. The first is: What knowledges are and how are them related to the
world? The self-steering and self-organisation of the knowledge come up with
the assumption of a cognition achieved by way of a closed and autopoietic brain.
For that reason,
knowledge emerges in the moment of acting. Knowledge in no way is encoding or
representation. This is to be understandable on the above exposition of the German
Idealism's and constructivism's theory of knowledge. Then the question follows,
for how the structure of knowledge looks like and how does it come into being. At
any analysis of the knowledge, its embeddedness in the social context has to be
taken into account, and an overall picture has also to be modelled. The
physical, psychological, and social components merge into each other, a fact
that has already been commented.
A further
question touches the maximal support for knowledge acquisition. Also for this
question there is already an answer. School and teachers are only allowed to
provide instruction aimed to promote the learning. Further consequences are
connected with the authenticity of the notices, and their situatedness; also,
with the multiple contexts, multiple perspectives, and social context. In order to really reach
right now some reduction of sluggish knowledge and a rise in the ability of
transferring knowledges, it results essential to abide by the following basic
assumption.
Namely, cognitive
construction depends on previous knowledge, the available mental structures,
and the already existing convictions. So it might be difficult to change from
top to bottom the so called deep cores,
inasmuch as these are barely modificable intersections of fundamental axioms,
normative as well as ontological.[93]
With regard to such ’deep cores’, the cognitive maps – in the
sense of convictions – are barely changeable. Knowledge, in each case, is
moreover constructed by the single incumbent person: on her or his own. In the
individual, a permanent need exists of linking every new knowledge with the
older ones and the connotations are socially conditioned, whence multiple
possibilities of interpretation are possible. All this leads to different results
of learning in the different pupils. It becomes necessary some applicative
connectionship of the learned, and such an application relationship exists, e.g., in a so called narrative anchor. Intense demands press
onto the learner in the teaching and learning process corresponding to the view
outlined here. The significance of the metacognitive abilites of reflection and
control of the active learning is very high. The learner ought to be able of
controlling and reflecting on her or his own learning and learning-process.
Still further,
and more concrete, practical consequences for shaping the environmental
conditions of a constructive learning can be now derived from what was already
said. Under the term authenticity
gets along the insight, that realistic problems and authentic situations have
to be generated to serve as frame, and context of application, for the
knowledges to be acquired. In turn,
multiple contexts means that the learner is to apply the learned knowledge
flexibly, and on different contexts. Under multiple
perspective reference is made to the insight, that curricular contents are
looked at – and dealt with – under different aspects and from different
viewpoints. Social context
definitively taps on the learning process' setting: this setting, environment,
or atmosphere of the learning process, in learning groups fosters cooperative
learning and collective problem-solving. Learning in common means, that the
learning takes place in the form of, e.g.,
work in group or, maybe, partner work.
The contents (of
learning) should not become immune against critiques. This comes from the
requisite that the student enjoys the maximum of possible degrees of freedom. Moreover
the student must be allowed to build her or his own cognoscitive constructions,
interpretations and experiences. As already said, also the degrees of freedom
have to be recognized as such. This is so, because in the constructivistic
understanding of learning, both the subjectively experienced situation and the
room for practical action (which must be used!) are relevant. Constructivistic
pedagogy always requires a practical orientation of the curriculum.
With this, all
those conventional didactic methods such as frontal schooling became excluded,
in which the teacher mediates the facts in the form of conversational
instruction, by lecturing and by asking-developing the topics. Orientation to action
means that „the teacher feasibilizes that the learner educates herself or
himself independently" [94]. Therefore in constructivist pedagogy it is valid to
affirm that „If learning takes place autopoietically, then the own creativity
of the participants must be given as much place as possible in organized learning
situations. A didactic of feasibilizing [...], principally, has to
be preferred to a didactic of teaching." [95]
One might have heard of that, in some non-European countries, the autopoietic-constructivist
pedagogy is not seldom rejected, on the misunderstanding that its prefiguration
of the students' closure favors to engross, or immerse, the native students
into a purely social world and into the production of services, rather than
into the primary or the industrial production areas. Thus, specially in populations
that previously had achieved a high educational level, the autopoietic-constructivist
pedagogy finds objectors, who assume that it cloaks the political aim of
facilitating domination by way of intensifying the influence of the social control
media among the natives, while diminishing their possibilities of discovering
and exploiting by themselves non-social facts, i.e. in physics, chemistry, high technology, etc., that could
undermine their exclusion and enfeeble their being dominated. While every
technique, pedagogical or not, lends itself to misuse, any similarity, in the
reality, to such situation would only join constructivism in its stressing the
importance of context in education. Nonetheless, by orienting the education
toward action, one can as soon as possible do justice also to the achievements
of the empirical pedagogy. This is so, because the learner's connotational
world is different from the teacher's one, and too because each learner is in a
learning situation that differs from that of the other learners.[96]
To sum all this
up, one might retain these notions: Knowledge acquisition is a constructive
process, and learning an active process based on experience. With it no longer
the teacher, but the learner and the knowledge, are in the centre of attention.
Constructivism explains the relationships among which the to-be-acquired
knowledge is to function: "The art of teaching has little to do with the
transfer of knowledge; its fundamental aim has to be educating the art of learning."
[97]
In this respect, it is the view of constructivist pedagogy that the teacher
must become a developer of competence. This means that, along the lessons, also
technical, methodological, social, and personal accompanying competences are
developed, the teacher being there a supplier of knowledge that understands
itself as a process-helper and process-companion.[98]
___
Copyright © September 2007 Electroneurobiología. Diese Forschungsarbeit ist öffentlich zugänglich. Die treue Reproduktion
und die Verbreitung durch Medien ist nur unter folgenden Bedingungen gestattet:
Wiedergabe dieses Absatzes sowie Angabe der kompletten Referenz bei
Veröffentlichung, inklusive der originalen Internetadresse (URL, siehe oben). /
Este texto es un artículo de acceso público; su copia exacta y redistribución por cualquier medio
están permitidas bajo la condición de conservar esta noticia y la referencia
completa a su publicación incluyendo la URL (ver arriba). / This is an Open
Access article: verbatim copying and redistribution of this article are
permitted in all media for any purpose, provided this notice is preserved along
with the article's full citation and URL (above).
Accepted: 21 September 2007
revista
Electroneurobiología
ISSN:
0328-0446
[1]
Stefan Schweizer, Deutscher Idealismus,
Autopoiese und Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Electroneurobiologia 2007; 15 (1), pp. 3-62.
[2]
Pia-Johanna Schweizer/Stefan Schweizer,
Idealistisch geprägte Axiomatik des Selbstorganisationsparadigmas, in: Berichte
zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 29 (1) 2006, pages 53-66 und Stefan Schweizer,
Politische Steuerung selbstorganisierter Netzwerke. Baden-Baden 2003, pp. 85-98.
[3]
Sander, W. Politik in der Schule. Kleine
Geschichte der politischen Bildung. Lizenzausgabe für die Bundeszentrale für
politische Bildung. Bonn 2003, page 158.
[4]
One at least can often see the
Platonic-Aristotelic difference of opinion, about idealism and
realism/empirism, as the starting point for agreement or disagreement with regard
to the constructivism.
[5]
A point by Steffen Dietzsch, Deutscher Idealismus, in: Peter Prechtl /
Franz-Peter Burkhard, Metzler-Philosophie-Lexikon. Begriffe und Definitionen.
Stuttgart 1999, page 104.
[6]
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft.
Hamburg 2003, page 406.
[7]
Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena. Illinois 1989, page 134.
[8]
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft.
Hamburg 2003, pp. 838 f.
[9]
Volker Gerhardt, Kant, Immanuel, in: Metzler-Philosophen-Lexikon. Von den Vorsokratikern
bis zu den neuen Philosophen. Stuttgart
1995, page 439.
[10] Immanuel Kant,
Prolegomena. Illinois 1989, page 80.
[11]
Lothar Pikulik, Frühromantik. Epoche – Werke – Wirkung. München 2000 page 34.
[12]
Jean Grondin, Kant zur Einführung. Hamburg 1994, pp. 48 f.
[13]
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. Hamburg 2003, page 58.
[14]
Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena. Illinois 1989, page 13.
[15]
Vergleiche Axel Görlitz/Hans-Peter Burth, Politische Steuerung. Opladen 1998, page
226.
[16]
Axel Görlitz/Hans-Peter Burth, Politische Steuerung. Opladen 1998, pp. 206 f.
[17]
Manfred Frank, Einführung in die frühromantische Ästhetik. Frankfurt a. M.
1989, p.14.
[18]
Ibid., pp. 14 f.
[19]
Paul Carus, Kant's Philosophy, in: Immanuel Kant: Prolegomena. Illinois 1989, page
186.
[20]
Urban Wiesing, Kunst oder Wissenschaft? Konzeptionen der Medizin in der
deutschen Romantik. Stuttgart-Bad
Cannstatt 1995, page 147.
[21]
Ibid.,page 145.
[22]
Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Die Bestimmung
des Menschen. Hamburg 2000, page 32.
[23]
Wilhelm G. Jacobs, Johann Gottlieb
Fichte, in: Johann Gottlieb Fichte: Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre.
Hamburg 1994, page 51.
[24]
Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg
1994, page 205.
[25]
"Ich und meine Welt sind das Produkt meiner freien Tätigkeit." Cf. Helmut Seidel, Fichte zur
Einführung. Hamburg 1997, page 47.
[26]
"… er erschafft eine Welt aus dem Nichts; denn es gibt nur das Ich des Geistes.
Durch dieses Ich entsteht die Welt. Cf.
Johannes Hirschberger, Kleine Philosophie Geschichte. Freiburg/Basel/Wien 1980,
page 156.
[27]
Klaus Peter, Romantik, in: Eberhard Bahr (Hrsg.), Geschichte der deutschen
Literatur. Von der Aufklärung bis zum Vormärz (2. Band) Tübingen/Basel 1998, page
352.
[28]
Wilhelm Jacobs, Einleitung, in: Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Grundlage der gesamten
Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg 1997, page XI.
[29]
Johann Gottlieb Fichte, „Das Streben des Ich kann nicht gesetzt werden, ohne
daß ein Gegenstreben des Nicht-Ich gesetzt werde; denn das Streben des ersteren
geht aus auf Kausalität, hat aber keine; und daß es keine hat, davon liegt der
Grund nicht in ihm selbst, denn sonst wäre das Streben desselben kein Streben,
sondern Nichts.“ Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg 1997, page 205.
[30]
Lothar Pikulik, Frühromantik. Epoche – Werke – Wirkung. München 2000, page 37.
[31]
Manfred Boin, Fichte, in: Metzler-Philosophen-Lexikon. Von den Vorsokratikern
bis zu den neuen Philosophen. Stuttgart 1995, page 277.
[32]
Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Grundlage d. g. Wissenschaftslehre. Hamburg 1997, page 146.
[33]
Peter Sloterdijk, Vorbemerkung, in: Michaela Boenke, Schelling. München 2001, page
13.
[34]
Walter Schulz, Einleitung, in. Friedrich Schelling, System des transzendentalen
Idealismupage Hamburg 2000, page XXI.
[35]
Franz Josef Wetz, Schelling zur Einführung. Hamburg 1996, page 31.
[36]
„Alles Wissen beruht auf der Übereinstimmung eines Objektiven mit einem Subjektiven".
Friedrich Schelling, System des transzendentalen Idealismus. Hamburg 2000, page
9.
[37]
"So gewiß also alles Wissen überhaupt auf jenem Gegensatz der Intelligenz
und des Objekts beruht, so gewiß kann jener Gegensatz in keinem Objekt sich
aufheben ... Die Intelligenz kann nie ins Unendliche sich ausbreiten, denn
daran wird sie verhindert durch ihr Streben, in sich zurückzukehren. Sie kann
aber ebensowenig absolut in sich selbst zurückkehren, denn daran verhindert sie
jene Tendenz, das Unendliche zu sein." Friedrich Schelling, System des
transzendentalen Idealismus. Hamburg 2000, page 149.
[38]
Urban Wiesing, Kunst oder Wissenschaft? Konzeptionen der Medizin in der
deutschen Romantik. Stuttgart-Bad
Cannstatt 1995, page 191.
[39]
Johannes Hirschberger, Kleine Philosophie Geschichte. Freiburg/Basel/Wien 1980,
page 160.
[40]
Walter Schulz, Einleitung, in: Friedrich Schelling, System des transzendentalen
Idealismupage Hamburg 2000, page XXVI.
[41]
Urban Wiesing, Kunst oder Wissenschaft? Konzeptionen der Medizin in der
deutschen Romantik. Stuttgart-Bad
Cannstatt 1995, page 143.
[42]
„um die Wissenschaft von sich selbst organisierenden Organisationen oder
Systemen, die erklärt, wie durch elementare Wechselwirkung Ordnung entsteht und
erhalten wird. Analog zu Schelling werden Natur und Erkennen begriffen als sich
selbst organisierende Systeme". Michaela Boenke, Über Schelling, in:
Michaela Boenke, Schelling. München 2001, page 36.
[43] As one
of such infrequent approaches, cf.
Pia- Johanna Schweizer/Stefan Schweizer, Idealistisch geprägte Axiomatik des
Selbstorganisationsparadigmas, in: Berichte zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte. Band
29 (1), page 53-66.
[44]
Humberto Maturana, Biologie der Sprache, in: Humberto Maturana: Biologie der Realität.
Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 132.
[45]
„die in Fortsetzung skeptischer und konstitutionstheoretischer Überlegungen
jegliche Form der Erkenntnis - einschließlich des Erkannten selbst - als
Konstruktion eines Beobachters begreift. Erkennen meint nicht die passive
Abbildung einer äußeren objektiven Realität, sondern bezeichnet einen Prozeß
der eigenständigen Herstellung bzw. Konstruktion einer kognitiven Welt ... Die
reale Welt als solche ist keine erfahrbare Wirklichkeit; Wirklichkeit ist
vielmehr immer wahrgenommene, beobachtete, erfundene, also konstruierte
Wirklichkeit". Georg Kneer, Radikaler Konstruktivismus, in:
Metzler-Philosophie-Lexikon. Begriffe und Definitionen. Stuttgart 1999, page 487.
[46]
„Einfach ausgedrückt handelt es sich um eine unkonventionelle Weise die
Probleme des Wissens und Erkennens zu betrachten. Der Radikale Konstruktivismus
beruht auf der Annahme, daß alles Wissen ... nur in den Köpfen von Menschen
existiert und daß das denkende Subjekt sein Wissen nur auf der Grundlage
eigener Erfahrung konstruieren kann. Was wir aus unserer Erfahrung machen, das
allein bildet die Welt, in der wir bewußt leben". Ernst von Glasersfeld,
Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Ideen, Ergebnisse, Probleme. Frankfurt am Main
1997, page 22.
[47]
Ernst von Glasersfeld, Drittes Siegener Gespräch über Radikalen
Konstruktivismus, in: Ernst von Glasersfeld, Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Ideen,
Ergebnisse, Probleme. Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 324.
[48]
Siegfried Schmidt, Vorwort, in: Ernst von Glasersfeld: Radikaler
Konstruktivismupage Ideen, Ergebnisse, Probleme. Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 12.
[49]
For the ensuing, compare Siegfried Schmidt, Vorwort, in: Ernst von Glasersfeld,
Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Ideen, Ergebnisse, Probleme. Frankfurt am Main
1997, pp. 12 f.
[50] Again
it becomes clear, that the relations to German idealism in these basic
presupposition cannot be neglected.
[51]
At this point, radical constructivism is closer than idealism to the “theory of
autopoiesis“, which precisely stresses the social area of interaction!
[52]
Ernst von Glasersfeld, Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Ideen, Ergebnisse,
Probleme. Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 96.
[53]
The concept of viability assumes neutrality as regards the concept of survival.
[54]
[Die Funktion der] „Kognition ist adaptiver Art, und zwar im biologischen Sinne
des Wortes, und zielt auf Passung oder Viabilität". Ernst von Glasersfeld,
Radikaler Konstruktivismupage Ideen, Ergebnisse, Probleme. Frankfurt am Main
1997, p. 96.
[55]
„Konstruktivisten ... betrachten alles Wissen als instrumental. Als erstes
sollten daher dem Lernenden die Gründe vermittelt werden, warum bestimmte
Weisen des Handelns und Denkens als wünschenswert betrachtet werden. Daraus
folgt notwendig die Erklärung der spezifischen Zusammenhänge, in denen das zu
erwerbende Wissen angeblich funktionieren soll." Ibid.,page 284.
[56]
Ibid.,page 309.
[57]
Wolfgang Singer, Der Beobachter im Gehirn. Frankfurt am Main 2002, pp. 168 f.
[58]
Gerhard Roth, Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt am Main 1997, pp. 314
ff.
[59]
Humberto Maturana/Francisco Varela, Der Baum der Erkenntnis. München 1992, pp. 50
f.
[60]
Humberto Maturana/Francisco Varela, Der Baum der Erkenntnis. München 1992, page
54.
[61]
Ulrich Druwe, Politische Theorie. Neuried 1995, page 349.
[62]
Humberto Maturana, Einführung, in: Humberto Maturana, Biologie der Realität.
Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 20.
[63]
Humberto Maturana/Francisco Varela, Der Baum der Erkenntnis. München 1992, page
54.
[64]
Humberto Maturana, Ontologie des Beobachtens, in: Humberto Maturana, Biologie
der Realität. Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 183.
[65]
Humberto Maturana/Francisco Varela, Der Baum der Erkenntnis. München 1992, page
55.
[66]
Humberto Maturana, Ontologie des Beobachtens, in his Biologie der Realität,
cit. p. 182.
[67]
Cf. Bergmann, A., Erklärungspragmatik
und politische Steuerung. Berlin 2001, page 199.
[68]
Humberto Maturana, Biologie der Kognition, in: H. Maturana: Biologie der
Realität. Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 26.
[69]
Maturana, H., Ontologie des Beobachtens, in his Biologie der Realität, cit., page
183.
[70]
Burth, H.P., Steuerung unter der Bedingung struktureller Koppelung. Opladen
1999, page 162.
[71] Maturana, H., Realität,
in his Biologie der Realität. Frankfurt am Main 2000, pp. 244 f.
[72]
Cf. here Görlitz, A., Burth, H.-P.,
Politische Steuerung. Opladen 1998, page 209.
[73]
Maturana, H., Ontologie des Konversierens, in: Humberto Maturana: Biologie der
Realität. Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 362.
[74]
Maturana, H., Ontologie des Beobachtens, in: Humberto Maturana: Biologie der
Realität. Frankfurt am Main 2000, page 202.
[75]
Cf. Burth, H.-P., Steuerung unter der
Bedingung Struktureller Koppelung. Opladen 1999, page 206.
[76]
"Und daß Wahrnehmungen wie Theorien nichts als Konstruktionen des Gehirns
bzw. der Gehirne der Wissenschaftler sind – erst einmal ganz unabhängig von
einer irgendwie gearteten "objektiven" Wirklichkeit und nur entlang
der inneren Prozesse und Reproduktionsbedingungen, der Autopoiesis, der
Selbstkonstruktionen der Gehirne und der sie tragenden Organismen." Hartmut
Esser, Soziologie. Allgemeine Grundlagen. Frankfurt am Main 1999, page 54.
[77]
Siegfried Schmidt, Vorwort. Frankfurt am Main 1997, pp. 12 f.
[78]
For the following cf. Back-Haas, A.,
Konstruktivismus als didaktischer Aspekt der Berufsbildung, in: Bonz, B.
(Hrsg.), Didaktik der beruflichen Bildung, Baltmannsweiler 2001, pp. 220-238.
[79]
Cf. Heinz v. Foerster (Hrsg.),
Einführung in den Konstruktivismus, Zürich 1985.
[80]
Cf. Pongratz, L., Untiefen im
Mainstream. Zur Kritik konstruktivistisch-systemtheoretischer Pädagogik,
Giessen 2005.
[81]
Die Erziehungswissenschaft „kann im Grunde nur jene 'Konstruktionen' aufarbeiten,
d.h. alle Mythen und Wissensfragmente, auf die die Pädagogik stolz ist." Gudjons,
H., Pädagogisches Grundwissen. Bad Heilbrunn 2001, page 47.
[82]
"Danach ist das Subjekt (als lebendes System) alleiniger Urheber des
Wissens, seiner Konstitution und Konstruktion. Der Mensch konstruiert seine
Welt, in der er lebt, selbstreferentiell und autopoietisch." Gudjons, H.,
Pädagogisches Grundwissen. Bad Heilbrunn 2001, pp. 46 f.
[83]
Peter Prechtl, Behaviorismus, in: Peter Prechtl / Franz-Peter Burkhard,
Metzler-Philosophie-Lexikon. Begriffe und Definitionen. Stuttgart 1999, page 69.
[84]
Wolf Singer, Der Beobachter im Gehirn. Franlfurt am Main 2002, page 168 f.
[85]
Gerhard Roth, Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 314
ff.
[86]
Gerhard Roth, Das Gehirn und seine Wirklichkeit. Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 333.
[87]
"Jegliche Wahrnehmungsprozesse sind selbstorganisierend". Wolf
Singer, Der Beobachter im Gehirn. Frankfurt am Main 2002, page 167.
[88]
Huwendiek, V., Didaktik: Modelle der Unterrichtsplanung, in: Huwendiek, V.,
Bovet, G., (Hrsg.), Leitfaden Schulpraxipage Pädagogik und Psychologie für den
Lehrberuf. Berlin 2000, page 36.
[89]
Zum Paradox der Steuerung autopoietisch geschlossener Einheiten Cf. Stefan
Schweizer, Politische Steuerung selbstorganisierter Netzwerke.
[90]
Sander, W., [Lernen gilt im Konstruktivismus als] „konstruktive Leistung der
Individuen [...], die von Lehrenden angeregt und begleitet, nicht aber
gesteuert werden kann. Zur professionellen Aufgabe von Lehrenden gehört es
dann, solche Lernumgebungen zu
planen, die erfolgreiches Lernen ermöglichen und dieses Lernen zu begleiten.“ Politik in der Schule.
Kleine Geschichte der politischen Bildung. Lizenzausgabe für die Bundeszentrale
für politische Bildung. Bonn 2003, page 157.
[91]
Wenn Lernen als „Selbstentwicklung eines kognitiven Systems" (Aufschnaiter)
verstanden wird, können Eigenverantwortung und aktive innere Verarbeitung gar
nicht wichtig genug genommen werden." Huwendiek, V., Didaktik: Modelle der
Unterrichtsplanung, "Die alte Vorstellung der Fremdsteuerung gilt es zu
revidieren", in: Huwendiek, V., Bovet, G. (Hrsg.), Leitfaden Schulpraxipage
Pädagogik und Psychologie für den Lehrberuf. Berlin 2002, page 36.
[92]
Back-Haas, A., Konstruktivismus als didaktischer Aspekt der Berufsbildung, in:
Bonz, B. (Hrsg.), Didaktik der beruflichen Bildung, Baltmannsweiler, 2001, page
225.
[93]
Compare with the concept of deep core:
P.A. Sabatier, Advocacy-Koalitionen, in: Héritierm A. (Hrsg.), Policy-Analyse.
Opladen 1993, page 116 ff.
[94]
Huggenschmidt, B., Technau, A.: „dass der Lehrende dem Lernenden ermöglicht,
sich selbstständig einzubringen.“ In: Methoden schnell zur Hand. 66 schüler-
und handlungsorientierte Unterrichstmethoden, Stuttgart u. Leipzig 2005, page 12.
[95]
Wehner, M., „Wenn Lernen autopoietisch stattfindet, dann muss in organisierten
Lernsituationen der Eigenkreativität von Teilnehmern möglichst viel Raum
gegeben werden. Eine Ermöglichungsdidaktik [...] ist prinzipiell einer
Belehrungsdidaktik vorzuziehen.“ In: Das Jugendprojekt LUPO – Demokratie
lustvoll erleben und lernen, in: Breit, G., Schiele, page (Hrsg.)
Demokratie-Lernen als Aufgabe der politischen Bildung. Lizenzausgabe für die
Bundeszentrale für politische Bildung, Bonn 2002, page 303.
[96]
Schelle, C., Einstellungen von Schülern und Schülerinnen zu Gesellschaft,
Politik und Demokratie – Hermeneutische Rekonstruktionen und Konsequenzen für
die Fachdidaktik, in: Breit, G., Schiele, page (Hrsg.) Demokratie-Lernen als
Aufgabe der politischen Bildung. Lizenzausgabe für die Bundeszentrale für
politische Bildung, Bonn 2002, page 119.
[97]
E. v. Glasersfeld, "Die Kunst des Lehrens hat wenig mit der Übertragung
von Wissen zu tun, ihr grundlegendes Ziel muss darin bestehen, die Kunst des
Lernens auszubilden." In: Radikaler
Konstruktivismupage Frankfurt am Main 1997, page 309.
[98]
Huggenschmidt, B., Technau, A., Methoden schnell zur Hand. 66 schüler- und
handlungsorientierte Unterrichstmethoden, Stuttgart, Leipzig 2005, page 19.