Gobierno de la ciudad de Buenos Aires
Hospital Neuropsiquiátrico
"Dr. José Tiburcio Borda"
Laboratorio de Investigaciones Electroneurobiológicas
y
Revista
Electroneurobiología
ISSN: 0328-0446
On minds’ localization
Clues from a range of
academic topics suggest that observers are put in operative connection or disconnection
with the surrounding occurrences by the physiologically modulated motion of
unidentified microphysical particles
by
Mario Crocco
Correspondence / Contacto: Postmaster [-yat--] neurobiol.cyt.edu.ar
Electroneurobiología
12 (3), pp. 244-257, 2004 ; URL http://electroneubio.secyt.gov.ar/index2.htm
Copyright ©2004
This file does not keep original formats and page numbers. You may read,
print or save this research paper in .PDF
(401 kB: recomendada) or .DOC (217
kB) versions.
ABSTRACT: A confluence of clues from a
range of academic topics suggests that minds localization in nature consists of
relativistically moving microphysical particles, whose motion is physiologically
modulated. Here those clues are shown to imply that the localization of the operations
of observers (minds or existentialities) in nature are the actions carriers of
a force field, which action carriers are slightly slowed from near-c
speed motion by electroneurobiological variations in brain physiology – thus
gating through relativistic time dilation the observer’s time resolution and
putting her or him in operative connection or disconnection with the surrounding
occurrences. In this scenario, minds as well as sensory knowledge acquire a precise
definition and appear situated in a particular point of causal sequences.
Summary in general terms: Why were minds selected to turn accidents into opportunities, i. e.,
to progress toward biological goals through appropriate steps for which the
instructions are nonetheless undefinable? Minds appear situated in certain
force-carrying particles whose speed sets wakefulness or sleep. Through this
force, observable by its influence on the evolutionary process, minds and
bodies interact. Physical actions impinging on a mind generate in it physical
reactions whose causal efficiency gets exhausted, so that the reactions cannot
continue their causal series. In exchange, they become sensorially known. On
them the mind then takes efficient initiatives – whereby minds acquire
intellectual development – generating changes. The broken causal sequence
seems to be what enables minds for their biological role.
Summary in technical terms: Observers’ localization in nature might be relativistically moving particles whose motion
is physiologically modulated. Transdisciplinary clues imply that speed
variation is imposed onto some action carriers of a force field by their
coupling with intensity variations of an overlapping field. The operations of
observers (minds or existentialities) in nature seem localized in such actions
carriers, slightly slowed from near-c speed motion by
electroneurobiological variations – which thus gate the observer’s time resolution
and put her or him in operative connection or disconnection with the
surroundings. Thereby minds and sensory knowledge appear in a particular point
of causal sequences.
_________________________
[This written exposition comes from
a wide-ranging lecture
summarizing the articulation of several
concepts more detailedly expounded in other articles of this journal. Ed.]
1. What is observed?
Cows and cars continue causal
series coming from their milieu: both of them resume chemical reactions, from the remote past when burning off fossil fuel and from
more recent photosyntheses when chewing grass. News reported in this article allow us to better tell apart a cow from a car. The physical
actions impinging from outside on the cow’s psyche generate in it what now
appears as a special type of physical reactions, called intonations, whose
causal efficiency gets exhausted – so that they cannot continue the causal
series. In exchange, they get sensorially known. The cow’s mind may then take
physically efficient initiatives – the ones whereby minds acquire intellectual
development – generating variations, in quantity or distribution of the
motion they originate, as an effect of internal forces. This appears to be why,
during the course of evolution, minds become selected as the uppermost
regulatory level of organisms thriving in environments that impel these
organisms to overcome the Turing machine’s limits (i. e., to progress
toward adaptive goals through appropriate steps for which the instructions are
nonetheless undefinable), acquiring the ability to turn accidents into opportunities.
Those forces can be observed by their influence on the evolutionary process,
and their action carriers’ features are found constrained by a number of
neuropsychological and clinical observations.
2. Reciprocal constraints of separate findings
In a dozen independent academic
fields, hints have recently surfaced whose combination suggests that the
unknown localization of minds in nature features certain characteristics, the most
remarkable of which is motion. It comes from the following observations:
1. Genetic epistemology is
generally considered a branch of psychology, chiefly developed in the last
three quarters of the 20th century by the efforts of the
biologist-psychologist Jean Piaget[1], [2]
and many collaborators. Their work shows that minds achieve intellectual development
through behavioral probing of reality, not through its Platonic contemplation.
The focus of the minds’ description thus shifted onto the origination of probing
actions, or initiatives, a feature distinguishing minds from non-minds and
discussed below. Whatever it is that senses, it proceeds as if enclosed in a
supple bag: in this case, only by taking initiatives, i.e. by palpating
the bag’s wall, can it recognize what is invariantly conserved outside and, so,
build a mental map or picture of the surrounding happenings.
2. Evolution of living systems, one of the most notable dynamical phenomena
of nature, is a physical relaxation process. As such, it should move on a
shortest path amid environmental circumstances whose variety on Earth may be
considered quite constant since at least Late Proterozoic times.
3. Combination
of the preceding observations suggests that minds are not epiphenomenal but do
efficiently act in the surroundings, collectively behaving as a physical force
that – also because the assemblage of mind-guided actions is never fully
adapted or identically conformed to biological usefulness – modifies the
shortest path of the biosphere’s evolutionary relaxation process. By
differently setting its minimal trajectory, minds act as a Newtonian force,
observed in their biological effects which include stretching the trophic
chains and anthropogenic perturbations.
4. This
implies that the mentioned mind’s initiatives – whereby minds acquire
intellectual development – are variations, in quantity or distribution of
the motion they originate, as an effect of internal forces. It is upon this
feature that biological evolution functionalizes, or uses as a means, the
regular appearings of existentialities (or subjective existences, or psyches)
for overcoming the limitations of Turing machines, which are unable to convert
accidents into opportunities. This function is for some organisms the foremost
among the so called “functions of relation with the environment,” or functions
of relation for short. For nourishing, defending and reproducing themselves
most biological organizations operate as Turing machines, namely as
contrivances that cast step by step their outcomes’ string. As such do
function, e.g., corals, oysters, and tropical plants, all of which are
usually construed as not mind-regulated living creatures. These biological
organizations solve their problems upon species-specific preadaptations;
namely, all their functions of relation are preset. So, oysters solve these
problems of how to nourish, defend and reproduce by basing their particular
solutions on species-specific preadaptations, instead of minding of the
situations they should cope with. In contrast, by refining the adaptation or
adequacy of the provided solutions, in the biological organisms called
“mind-regulated animals” – each of which uses a mind as its uppermost
regulatory level – the individual existentiality that confronts a concrete
problem does this, and grasps at many of the opportunities that a Turing
machine would have lost. The mind’s continual forwarding of initiatives – the
mentioned probings “through the bag’s wall” – that allows their Piagetian
intellectual development physically requires that minds’ specific actions
belong with an interaction modality, whose action carriers should be those of
the Newtonian force observed to influence the path of the biosphere’s evolutionary
relaxation process.
5. On the
other hand, clinical observations show recoveries from amnesias. This old observation,
in the recently acquired scenario thus far outlined, entails that memories are
not engraved data, which – in spite of the fact that the name cerebrum
implies the engraving metaphor – could not be recovered after loss. The
mentioned findings of genetic epistemology require that any recovery after a
genuine loss be achieved by way of building anew the intellectual development,
which is manifestly not the case of recovered patients. This suggests that the
recoveries from amnesias should not be deemed recoveries of genuinely lost
mental contents, but reacquisitions of the brain’s ability to have them reimagined.
6. Far from
the study of amnesias on the academic map, physical studies on the origin of inertial
mass have been as yet inconclusive but most physicists agree that this mass
comes from outside onto elementary particles which by themselves are massless[3].
Although we are unaware of the mechanism[4],
it is observed that some particles hold a certain amount of mass and others
none. This situation allows time processes to spread up from microphysical
scales, i.e. the force fields’ action carriers can thereby arrange
structures that evolve in scales larger than microphysical.
7. But this
process has not been found to organize the internal differentiations of minds,
or mental contents. This suggests that such time processes do not course inside
minds and anything that achieves sensed or known differentiations “sediments”
them as its memories, altering itself by sedimenting
away from time its causal involvements. “Away from time” means “not on time
courses but inside the instant,” which instant is where such reality which
knows – as well as the whole of nature – occurs and simultaneizes the
sedimented sequences (“memories”) of its reactions to its causal interactions.
This is tantamount to saying that whichever reality that knows itself ought to
possess memory of what it knowingly differentiates; namely that, because nature
vacates itself outside actuality and so every thing and process in nature,
including each mind, only exists within the physical instant, the preservation
of memories is an effect of the absence of time course, not of the presence of
brain engrams. To put it still otherwise, it means that, in the same way that impetus
is superfluous to keeping unperturbed bodies in geodesic motion, engraving such
memories in the brain is superfluous to keeping them in mind.
8. The
interval-like duration of the physical instant, or time-like period in which no
physical action could ever insert a change, is unknown. Many physicists are
sympathetic toward the view that identifies it as the Planck instant, but in
present nature no separate force, or interaction modality whose relationships
enter to define the Planck instant, can produce a change before a “characteristic time” of some 1020 Planck instants or more: every transformation in
time is, thus, currently ticked on intervals always larger than this one. In
contrast, it is observed that moments, the least interval which an awake mind can distinguish or resolve and during which no
mental action can be done, have a magnitude of the order of the hundredth of a
second, about 1041 Planck instants.
3. Interval dilation in mind disconnections
This particular relationship
between such physical instants and mental moments, namely about 1041 times,
may be a relativistic dilation generated by moving close to a speed equal to c
minus a 10‑82 fraction of c. Further circumstances
suggest that this possibility should be seriously considered.
9. Besides this time acuity proper
of the attentional focus of an awake mind, we observe
states of inattention, sleep and coma that are usually interpreted as loses of
consciousness or, in the case of inattention, as a decrease in the sensed
objects’ “force of imposition”. As an academic expression, the latter is a
wording that acquired some biomedical denotations following its origin in
phenomenological introspection[5]
and might require explanation: what is in the focus of attention allows one to
be mindful of all that one knows that could be done with it (i.e., its
defining “concept”), while what is outside of the attentional focus is minded
as if one’s operative possibilities in its regard had been abridged into a referential
block, like substituting a complicated term in equations by a single letter or
a simple sign. This state of the fully sensed but faintly apperceived objects
is the decrease in their operational recognition in which the reduction of
their force of imposition consists. It, as well as the “losses of
consciousness” (sleep, general anesthesia, coma), may manifest variations in
the resolutive power or acuity, caused by variations in the said relativistic
dilation – not wholly unlike playing an old phonograph record at the wrong
speed.
10. On the other hand, during the
last four decades or so mentation has been reported to occur in all
electroencephalographic stages of sleep[6],
[7],
[8],
[9],
from falling asleep to waking, suggesting that during deep sleep no “loss” or
temporary cessation of mind occurs. This observation, in the context being
examined, allows us to conjecture that inattention consists of modifying the
mind’s resolutive power of the brain’s sectorial states that generate the
unattended sensations, while in turn sleep, swoon and coma involve an application
more intense and widely spread (e. g., over an entire hemisphere or the
whole brain) of the same mechanism. It could be achieved and regulated by way
of decreasing the fraction of c speed which is subtracted from c
for physiologically setting the velocity of the particles where the causal
involvements of minds find their most immediate localization, namely the
velocity of the action carriers exerting the Newtonian force observed to modify
the path of the biospheric relaxation process. This increment in speed would
change the dilation of the physical instant, from some 1041 times to
1045 times or more, preventing the observer from resolving several
minutes or more in extramental sequences, while her or his own time remains unaltered.
11. To establish any
verisimilitude in this conjecture, the mode of recovering from traumatic
amnesia in neuropsychiatric patients was expressly observed, benefiting from
the large quantity of cases in one of the institutions with which the present
author is affiliated. No novel findings surfaced and in most cases the
anterograde amnesia was indistinguishable from the effects of inattention, the
recovery appearing as compatible with what could be described as reacquisition
of the ability of putting and retaining at will the focus of attention on any
sector of experience.
12. Other common observations are
also congruent with viewing time acuity or resolutive power as the
brain-dependent factor gating the observer’s connection and disconnection with
the surroundings, in such a way that sleep, swoon, comas, and similar states
could disconnect minds from the environment by varying the mind’s
time-resolution of the brain’s neurodynamical sequences – the brain generating
this disconnecting variation by altering the relativistic dilations created by
the speed of the force carriers where minds find their most immediate
localization. One of such observations is that, while dreamt sensations are being
sensed those sensations coming from the sense organs are not. A
dream-originated fa note is sensed
but the same dreamer does not sense a fa note from the external world neurodynamically
enacted in the same brain. In the discussed scenario, this is exactly what
should occur because the first sensations become stirred by neuroactivity
patterned with the resolution of extramental time sequences of a dreaming mind,
while the second ones are stirred by neuroactivity that remains patterned with
the resolution of extramental time employed to keep track of the outer processes
of biological relevance.
In the same scenario, perceived features
“fade” due to inattention by altering the relativistic dilations created by the
speed of those force carriers in the brain areas that are generating features
of which the mind is to become inattentive. When “paying” attention to something,
what is contributed is the operationalizing of its sensations. One thereby
applies, to a sector of one’s sensory field, the acquired system of
equilibrable operations sedimented in one’s mind. And neuroactivity is expected
to lack mental concomitants when the time-structure of its patterns is not also
conserved in the dynamics of the physical field in whose force carriers minds find their most immediate localization. Thus,
in this outlook, inattention causes amnesia by texturing the mind with contents
whose time “graining” is not resolvable in the time-resolution of the mind’s
available operational combinations that conserve the object. Sleeping right
after learning, in this perspective, is thus better for retention than remaining
awake because the organization of memories reflects the time-resolution in
which the original experiences were lived: every time-resolution allows
reimagining the experiences from different time-resolutions, but just as
unattended context. Thus sleep prevents the ensuing waking life from
intervening and sleep mentation – physiologically supported on a different time
resolution – does not itself interfere. The same specific mechanism is also
expected (a) to prevent remembering most sleep mentation after awakening; (b)
to dissociate the ease of access or “handiness” of awake rememberings from
oneiric threads (and of oneiric episodes from awake decisions); (c) to put
distractions before forgetting at the beginning of dementedness processes; (d)
to confer status epilepticus more proclivity to anterograde than to retrograde
amnesia; and (e), in traumatic memory deficits, to make depend the recall of
the pretraumatic (retrograde) portion of life, forgotten in a mnesic lacuna or
memory “lagoon,” on the same lacuna’s postraumatic (anterograde) portion or
“amnesia of fixation” period. In all these cases, in the scenario thus far
outlined, the biographical episodes lived from a certain time dilation can no
longer be operatively categorized in full when the relativistic speed state, of
the biophysical components that form their experiencer’s immediate circumstance,
changes into another relativistic speed state.
The condition in which the brain
does not tune its electroneurobiology so as to furnish proper time dilation to
sensory experiences is understood to result, therefore, in a condition similar
to that involved in the fading, into “distraction,” of many memories of the
habitual life lived in the months or years after a catastrophic bereavement. At
their occurrence one perceives the sensory experiences just as one perceives
scarcely attended-to vehicle and pedestrian traffic around the bus in which one
travels. These scarcely attended-to vehicles and pedestrians are well seen,
heard and identified in some incipient detail but soon, even perhaps before one
gets out of the bus, one cannot put their perceptions in any order so as to
recall their presentation. The same occurs to all the life episodes lived in
some (often transient) postconcussive stages. Such a process is called
“distraction” when it intrudes on one´s plans, e. g. when, while
reading, one plays a disc with many songs and sometimes finds that the songs
which one most expected to hear are finishing, have been “heard,” yet their
memory – though recent – is irretrievable. In order to arouse the affects and
emotions one wished to obtain from the audition they should be played anew –
and listened to without reading. Preventing it is why, illustratively, theaters
impose silence and darken the seating precisely when performances commence. It
should be plain that in the discussed scenario “distraction” is what in
clinical contexts is called “fixation amnesia” or anterograde amnesia, namely
difficulties in learning new information. In the beginning of dementias it precedes
the older memories’ unreimaginability (forgetting), and in the outlined
scenario the same mechanism also conditions the possibilities of awake and
dreaming states for reciprocal recall. In sleep mentation it is also to bring about the “attentional
narrowing,” the thematic or experiential reduction that impoverishes one’s full
experience, shrinking the menu of other experiences that one keeps available
for collation with the actual contents of a dreamt thread in such a way that –
above and beyond more specific cognitional effects – while dreaming we are
habitually unaware that we are in fact in a dreamworld. On the same basis, it
also is to set the distribution, over the sleep period, of the dreams that
include “diurnal rests.”
Disparities in the force of
imposition, in view of the hints suggested by the observations under
commentary, are to reflect not absolute but proportional disparities in resolution.
This is suggested by the also common observation that the experiences that closely
precede powerful emotions, although acquired with unweakened force of
imposition, are as likely to be forgotten as those of the enthralling emotional
event’s experiential margin, which, instead, faded into “distraction” at
acquisition time. Such disparities so may make that people awakened after having
slept for more than a very short period cannot typically recall the last few
minutes before they fell asleep, and also make people prone to forget phone
calls or exchanges which they have had in the middle of the night, or the
alarm’s ringing in the morning if one fell immediately to sleep after turning
it off. In this setting, acquisition with decreased force of imposition is also
the reason why, of the memories “diluted” by anterograde amnesia, no recovery
is observed similar to the gradual reinstatement of pretrauma memories common
with retrograde amnesia.
Table 1 (p. 257) shows several further
observations in clinical and neurocognitive sciences congruent with the
portrayed scenario.
4. Definitions of 'mind' and
'sensory knowledge'
The preceding scenario furnishes
objective definitions of minds in general and of sensory knowledge, as follows.
Past and future situations only
rise in the context of minds. They do not exist outside of psyches: outside of
minds only present situations occur. Past and future situations are only
imagined, in a simplified way and certainly diversely. In this way – namely, by
their being imagined now – their reality is in fact a part of the present
situation; in this it exhausts itself. In other words, past and future situations
lack any other relevance for extramental reality, since they are neither found,
nor do they cause effects, except as assemblages of mental contents envisaged
by minds. Thus, all nature is actual only at a given instant, and each present
situation determines its own time transformation; nonexistent situations cannot
causally determine any transformation whatsoever. In this context, because any
supra-quantum indeterminacy in it is found to apply to future events, when
determining each next macroscopic transformation the actual or last situation
is tantamount to its entire preceding history.[10] In
contrast, minds change quite differently: minds, existentialities or psyches are the realities that transform
themselves only on a selection of their respective antecedents, not necessarily
on all of them. Turning the scales, the things we find situated amid
minds in nature (or things that compound the gap among minds’ operative
immediacies, or hylozoic hiatus; namely, all extramentalities such as winds,
rocks, fungi, trees, and computers, for which a variation in quantity or
distribution of motion cannot occur as an effect of internal forces) inevitably
use all of their history, tantamount to the last situation, to transform themselves
as time elapses. Thus while all their yesterdays pack into their now, all our tomorrows
are ours to shape. In finding the brute fact of this selection, physics finds
in nature the gnoseological apprehension and ability to inaugurate causal
series, enacting such selection. Both are found
to come conjointly, in discrete pops-out, whose efficient actions and reactions
become the natural phenomena we are trying to describe.
Gnoseological apprehension of
sensory mental contents, in general i. e. the act of knowing or noetic
act independently of who the mind is that performs it, is the feature of efficiently
causal interactions whereby the enacted structureless reactions intonate the
reacting entity on ranges whose manifestation exhausts the causal efficiency.
This knowledge or gnoseological apprehension grasps certain phenomenal reactions,
namely intonations of the self-knowing being, which cause to discontinue the
outer causal series that had led to them. Such a series of efficient causal
determinations comes to an end by producing intonative reactions, i. e.
phosphene-like manifestations that are both phenomenal (that is, in which a
sensation is known) and inefficient to continue the series.
5. The place of minds in
nature’s causal series
In the discussed scenario,
therefore, the emplacement of circumstanced existentialities in nature is found
whenever a break affects some efficient causal chain. The last link of this
chain phenomenizes as the reaction of an at least partly self-knowing being, a
reaction that becomes gnoseologically apprehended but lacks causal efficiency
to further its preceding causal series. As empirically found, outer causal
efficiency can work out intonative reactions in psychisms, but it cannot cause
psychisms to be affected in such a way as to instrumentally transmit the outer
efficiency. Any causal consequence from this outer efficiency is thus to be a
new causal string unpromptedly originated by the causal efficiency of the same
self-knowing being that had the gnoseological apprehension, and selected it as
a causal antecedent rather than deselecting it, or else adjusted it
contextually to posit it as a causal antecedent. Such events do not happen in
the hylozoic hiatus, where all of the causal series continue (i. e., all
causal efficiency is transeunt, matter-energy is conserved over effects) but,
in exchange, there is no gnoseological apprehension. In other words, by coming
to gnoseological apprehension, the causal series that led toward the intonative
reaction cannot continue any longer; an unprompted enactment of the efficient
causality of the same self-knowing reality is now needed to start another
causal series, which may enact continuity with or departure from the route of
the former causal series.
Always in the examined scenario,
and assuming a plausible understanding of causation (not to be discussed here),
one might question how privately accessible mental events can cause or be
caused by non-privately accessible physical events. The reason is, because
efficient causation is the same for both mental and physical events, as well as
across them. The mind↔brain causally-efficient
interaction is not more perplexing than the field generation of variations in
local potentials. In establishing, as initial causal link to set in motion some
course of regular extramental effects usually called “voluntary behavior,” the
local potentials of the field whose carriers are utilized by minds to launch
this causal series, every circunstanced mind does the same as all segregated
fields do everywhere but in the microphysical scale when, from an unlocalizable
set of determinations, they make themselves bring forth either more, or less,
of its force carriers at every spot of volume, thereby changing the spatial
distribution of their local potential (which in macroscopic scales may remain
stable on average). In setting up sensations the circumstanced mind’s immediate
field, on the same efficient causality, generates intonative reactions in the
mind.
But no dimensional mirroring of actions with reactions is conserved
across the brain-mind interface. Where no minds exist, actions and reactions
characterize each another with features from the same set. But in a nature that
includes operations originated by minds, intonations are found to result from
extramental actions that are depicted with a certain set of features, which
actions generate reactions depicted with another set of features.
This symmetry breaking is a very fundamental datum of the natural science
which attempts to describe a nature where the operations of minds are
encountered. We observe four segregated or diversified modalities of causal
interaction – also dubbed “basic forces,” being by name the strong nuclear
force, the weak nuclear force, the electromagnetic force, and the gravitational
force – in its actions outside us, and a further segregated modality of causal
interaction or “basic force,” namely the one which acts as a Newtonian force on
biospheric evolution and whose action carriers undergo the speed variations
that tune the mind’s time acuity, likewise from its actions outside of us (e.
g. its effects in biological evolution) but moreover from our reactions to
it. Such reactions are the mind’s subjective intonations, or sensational phenomena.
6. Ciliary control and nervous systems
As mentioned, to obtain
nourishment, defense and sex recombination, biological organisms enact their
distinctive menus of relationships with the external world by performing what
is called their “functions of relation.” Distinguishing any particular external
thing or sector to be acted or reacted upon (object) from the rest of the environment,
while allowing for its relevant relations with this environment (mapping), is
termed a “reference to object.” It was once thought that, for the functions of
relation to make reference to objects and map them, a nervous system was
requisite. Nervous systems, for that reason, became conceived as having started
with cellular specialization; that is, with the evolutionary selection of
surface cells specialized in detecting and cooperatively communicating the
presence of relevant objects to other bodily cells specialized in adaptively
dealing with them. Though functional, this criterion accentuated the primacy of
anatomical distinctions: the nervous systems were assumed to have started with
the functional diversity that made neurosensory cells different from other
cells – specially from motor cells. Otherwise stated,
it was thought that the natural selection of paths (hodologies, or neural nets)
for nerve activity supplied the physical processes to which minds can react by
intonating themselves subjectively. But the story is incorrect. Already in the
acellulars from which all animals derive, far before any cell differentiation
and presumably any subjectivity, the functions of relation made reference to objects.
These acellulars distinguished
from the rest of a mapped environment the particular thing or sector to be
acted or reacted upon. A good example is provided by hunters like Didinium nasutum which exhibits an insatiable appetite for paramecia. Propelled by its girdles of
cilia, barrel-shaped Didinium attacks paramecia horn first. Rapidly whirling through the water,
it then maneuvers its prey into a position in line with its cytostome,
ingesting the prey by opening its cytostome and swallowing it whole. Didinium
can swallow paramecia twice its size, and can repeat this remarkable
performance as many as a dozen times a day. Ciliophora,
thus, for over more than a thousand million years have
fed because the mechanism that controls cilia reorientates them or their water
currents toward fast swimming preys and edible floating crumbs. As the
means for attaining reference to objects, in the last phase of the chase they
utilized electric field patterns probably composed at the deformation of the
distribution of submembrane potential fluctuations – resulting from the
automatically coordinated ciliary beating – by the viscous contact of the
ciliary rows with a floating piece or the hydrostatic waves from also ciliated
preys. These means disappeared in many animal lineages, which instead formed
nervous ganglia as their uppermost level of organic regulation. Those means, on
the contrary, were preserved during the process of nervous path concentration
that formed brains, such organs looking like a feltwork of fibers in a soup of
enzymes[11] but
also tapping mind interactions. The
electropotential system for ciliary control was kept in the descendents that in
their larval stages (“dipleurula” [12],
[13], [14])
had the cilia around the “mouth”, i.e. in the ciliary band and the apical
organ. From the cells supporting these cilia, our nervous system comes. In it
we still retain not only the cilia but, also, gene sequences such as the one
called onecut [15], which,
anatomically, initiate the nervous system “above” what is to become the buccal
cavity in our early embryos.
As a result, always in the
discussed scenario, the brain organs that nowadays carry out the chordate’s
uppermost level of organic regulation include neural ganglia that subserve a specific,
connectivity-based function, which is not the uppermost regulatory function of
the organism: the neural ganglia embedded in each chordate brain do
hodologically enact unmindful behavior through refined sensomotor archs that
lack any memory of particular objects. As another result of the same course of
events brains also include the said electric field means. They perform another
specific function. These electric means furnish the therein circumstanced mind
both with exchanges to which to intonatively react and, also, with a pathway
for ecphoria, i.e. for causally chaining some extramental processes to
mental operations. Further, these very electric field means, by way of making
relativistic effects assume specific values at the locations of the
mind-extramentality causal exchanges, enact variations in time resolution that
modulate the mind’s intonative reactions, while the mind’s retentiveness (in
the context under commentary, no reason appears for assuming that memories
could succumb to time) supplies a memory of particular objects in terms of
their operative characterization. By that means individual intellectual
developments are enabled within the biosphere - whereupon the regular eclosions
of never regular minds get placed within the causal organization of behaving
organisms, as their uppermost regulatory level. Thereby, it is not through the
hodologies or circuitry of the neural ganglia embedded in the brain, that these
organisms become able to surmount the Turing machine limits and, so, colonize
biological niches where transforming accidents into opportunities is requisite
for survival.
7. Objections
Objections rise immediately
against the verisimilitude of this scenario. What is the separate force field
whose action carriers provide immediate localization to minds’ operative
efficiency? Ignoramus. In the discussed
perspective one can note that minds do not ride photons nor gluons because
these action carriers, being massless, cannot become decelerated or vary from
the c speed in the medium. Neither do minds ride W or Z particles because
the masses of these bosons are too large to generate by way of dilation the observed
relationships. This is so whether one takes as the time-like thickness of
nature the Planck instant or – on the other end of a possible range –
the characteristic time of some
interaction modality. Neutrinos and electrons are precluded, too. They are not
action carriers of force fields (they are classified as belonging with matter
fields). Furthermore, when taking the Planck instant as the time-like thickness
of nature, at the speeds assumed to produce the awake acuity dilation neutrinos
attain a dynamical mass of some four tons (1040 eV) each, while
electrons become 1041 MeV, or about 1011 kg each. Such
masses still increase by a factor of the order of a million at the speeds
assumed to produce deep-sleep acuity dilation. These particles remain precluded
even when less formidable prospects come into view by taking, as time-like
thickness of nature, the characteristic
times taken by the transition caused by, or specific delay of, some currently
segregated interaction modality (in which case the dilation factors,
between about 1020 for awake minds and 1024
in sleep mentation, would require speeds of between c – 10-40 c
and c – 10-48 c). Thus no clue has been identified for
matching the properties of any known species of fundamental particles with
those required for producing the mentioned effect.
Another
objection, redolent of the Bohr electron issue, observes that brain tissues are
not accelerators radiating in the gamma spectral band the energy needed to make
those particles to revolve so as to usefully remain inside the biological organ
while darting at those speeds. Those sharp turns, however, are uncalled for
inasmuch as individual particles become suitably substituted. Dragged by the sum of known astronomical motions at almost 400 km
per second[16],
the brain organ remains in Fermi scale-contact with a fixed volume or region of
its own size, of all physical fields, during ~10-21 second.
Into and out of this macroscopic region, but in the microphysical scale, all of
the overlapping physical fields bring the particles which set their respective,
overlapping potentials. Since the discussed scenario comes from a combination
of observational hints, seemingly one could only surmise that this short time
in contact with the same place suffices for the unknown force field coupled
with the electromagnetic one to engage by coupling into following the local
electromagnetic variational trends of potential variation.
A third and
more important objection takes for granted that, in order to bring in speed
fluctuations, physiology should influence barygenesis – i. e. generate
and wipe out inertial mass. It is correct to observe that the action carriers
where minds localize their causal exchanges must have a slight invariant mass,
namely the one allowing them to move at close to light speeds rather than c.
By modulating this speed, the fluctuations of electroneurobiological states are
to slow these action carriers down to the speed causing the time dilation
proper of awake minds’ attentional focus; in the
discussed scenario, when such a physiological action becomes physiologically
relaxed or pathologically impaired, relativistic dilation increases and minds
get disconnected from the surrounding causal courses. However, assuming that
the rest mass should vary is unnecessary. Putting aside the exotic supposition
that the brain’s electroneurobiological action could add inertial mass to these
action carriers so as to vary their invariant mass, leaves one with the
possibility of envisaging this effect just as a coupling varying their speed, i.e.
some absorption mechanism, redolent of a modulation of hysteresis loses, that
reduces the carriers’ dynamical mass by way of specific variational patterns of
the superimposed electric field – abstaining for the moment from further theorizing.
Finally, one
should observe that space, or dispersivity for forces, is not a cosmological
primitive: vast amounts of fresh space are being continuously created with the
expansion of the observable universe. What we can localize in space is action,
not the action’s determinations, whence “minds’s localization” means that we
localize the presence of some of mind’s operations, not that of their
determinations. Whether mental or not, the latter seem to eschew manifestation
in such a derivative occurrence, spatiality.
In conclusion, neuropsychological
observations, a part of the description of the evolution of living systems as
one of the most notable dynamic phenomena in nature, suggest a scenario in
which the localization of the operations of observers (minds or
existentialities) in nature are certain force-carrying particles whose speed,
physiologically modulated, sets the variations of wakefulness. Through this
force, observable by its influence on the evolutionary process, minds and
bodies interact: physical actions on a mind generate in it physical reactions
whose causal efficiency gets exhausted. As the reactions cannot continue their
causal series, they become sensorially known. Upon them the mind then takes
efficient initiatives – whereby it acquires intellectual development – setting
up broken causal sequences that enable minds for progressing toward biological
goals through appropriate steps for which the instructions are undefinable. For clinical practice, this scenario’s validity
means that the issue of “impaired consciousness” amounts to controlling the
tissue’s electroneurobiological activity that gates the proper acuity, thus
restoring the time-resolution matching. For physics, the present analysis can
provide a starting point for investigating the means enabling for biological
purposes the strangest things in cosmology, these existentialities, subjective
existences, minds or psyches.
[1] Piaget, Jean, Biologie et connaissance: essai sur les relations entre les regulations organiques et les processus cognitifs (Gallimard, Paris, 1967: collection « L’avenir de la science », # 42), cf. specially Chapter I and Chapter IV: 12. This and the following reference include Piaget’s two main summaries of his contributions from the standpoint of an evolutionary biologist.
[2] Piaget, Jean, Le comportement, moteur
de l’evolution (Gallimard, Paris, 1976: Collection « Idées »,
# 354).
[3]
[4] This continuing effect that extends time processes up from microphysics deserves to be called barygenesis (“origin of mass”), in contrast with the historical occurrence that originated the population of baryons (baryogenesis).
[5] E. g., philosopher X. Zubiri says “Every apprehension has its own force of imposition, and this imposition in the intellective state is knowing”. Taken from: <www.zubiri.org/works/englishworks/si/conclusion.htm>
[6] Nielsen, Tore A., A review of mentation in REM and NREM sleep: ‘covert’ REM sleep as a possible reconciliation of two opposing models – in Pace-Schott, Edward F.; Solms, Mark; Blagrove, Mark, and Harnad, Stevan, eds., Sleep and Dreaming: Scientific Advances and Reconsiderations (Cambridge University Press, 2003).
[7] Solms, Mark, Dreaming and REM Sleep are
controlled by different brain mechanisms, Behav. Brain Sci. 23 (6), 843-50; discussion 904-1121
(2000). Also published in Pace-Schott et al., eds
(see above reference).
[8] Conduit, Russell; Crewther, Sheila
Gillard, and Coleman, Grahame, Poor recall of eye-movement signals from Stage 2
compared to REM sleep: implications for models of dreaming, Conscious Cogn.
13 (3), 484-500 (2004).
[9] Takeuchi, T.; Miyasita, A., Inugami, M.; Yamamoto, Y., Intrinsic dreams are not produced without REM sleep mechanisms: evidence through elicitation of sleep onset REM periods, J. Sleep Res. 10 (1): 43-52 (2001).
[10] Sommerfeld, Arnold, Vorlesungen über theoretische Physik, Band 1: Mechanik (Akademische
Verlagsgesellschaft, Leipzig, 1943, p. 204)
[11]
Ashby, W. Ross, Some peculiarities of complex systems, Cybernetic
Medicine 9, pp. 1-7 (1973), p. 1.
[12] Garstang, Walter, Preliminary note on a new theory of the phylogeny of the chordata, Zool. Anz. 17, 122–125 (1894).
[13] Garstang, Walter, The morphology of the Tunicata and its bearing on the phylogeny of the Chordata, Q. J. Microsc. Sci. 72, 51–187 (1928).
[14]
Nielsen, C., Origin of the chordate central nervous system – and the
origin of chordates, Dev. Genes. Evol. 209, 198–205 (1999) .
[15]
Poustka, Albert J., Kühn, Alexander; Radosavljevic, Vesna;
Wellenreuther, Ruth; Lehrach, Hans, and
[16] Relative to a
shell of the observable universe some 13.7 Gyrs away. This is not
necessarily the velocity with respect to the local space; nevertheless, motions
inside our galactic supercluster alone add to ~300 km/s.
_____________________
Croquis de este sitio - Outline of this site
Índice - Table des
matières - Inhaltsverzeichnis - Table of Contents
Se recomienda mucho leer o imprimir algunos
de los trabajos mas extensos con el programa Acrobat Reader,
que puede obtenerse gratuitamente pulsando aqui
Haga doble
"click" en el título de cualquier artículo, para leerlo ahora -
Double-click on any article to read it now:
SOCIOLOGÍA DE LAS NEUROCIENCIAS
Pour comprendre l'enjeu : L’anthropologie ganglionnaire, un psychovirus démasqué (français)
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (190 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (76 kB).
L'aliénisme en Argentine : Diego Alcorta (1827) : Dissertation sur la manie... aiguë? (français)
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (600 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (320 kB).
Metaphors at odds in conceiving organismal-societal government: The Political Structure of the Brain: Cerebral Localization in Bismarckian Germany (English)
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (228 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (175 kB).
ELECTRONEUROBIOLOGÍA
Efectos relativísticos en biofísica cerebral:
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (496 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (227 kB)
SUMARIO Y PÁRRAFOS INICIALES EN CASTELLANO
Diversificación de recursos electroneurobiológicos en la evolución del sistema nervioso:
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (733 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (406 kB)
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (354 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (236 kB).
Cálculo de potenciales dentro de las células
Calcule intensidades eléctricas y magnéticas en cada compartimiento neuronal: The nervous principle: active versus passive electric processes in neurons (Explains how to calculate electric and magnetic field strengths inside different neuronal compartments) (LONG FILE IN ENGLISH with Bulgarian, Russian and Spanish abstracts/TOCs)
Podrá leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (2 Mb): recomendada) o .DOC (1,5 Mb). También como .html comprimido (compressed .HTML folder: 0,5 Mb) .ZIP.
NOCIONES GENERALES
Conceptos:
Comentando una "ilusión óptica" / Commenting an "optical illusion": A visual yet non-optical subjective intonation: una entonación subjetiva visual pero no óptica (English and Spanish)
Historia de las experimentaciones:
Table of Contents (partial) of "Sensing: a new fundamental action of nature" (English) -- Índices
Recepción de los aportes de Chr. Jakob en la neurobiología germana
You can download a .PDF (700 kB: recommended) or .DOC (1.3 MB) file for printing this work
You can download a .PDF (673 kB: recommended) or .DOC (1.29 MB) file for printing this work.
Puede obtener un archivo .PDF (256 kB: recommended) o .DOC (106 kB) para imprimir este trabajo.
Recepción de los aportes de Chr. Jakob en la neurobiología y la sociedad argentina
Piva y Virasoro - Christofredo Jakob, neurobiólogo: científico en diálogo filosófico (Spanish)
Puede obtener un archivo .PDF (391 kB: recommended) o .DOC (466 kB) para imprimir este trabajo.
Puede obtener un archivo .PDF (385 kB: recommended) o .DOC (813 kB) para imprimir este trabajo.
Puede obtener un archivo .PDF (384 kB: recommended) o .DOC (814 kB) para imprimir este trabajo.
Panorama evolutivo:
FILOSOFÍA DE LA CIENCIA - CONCEPTO DE TIEMPO EN NEUROBIOFÍSICA
You can download a .PDF (1 MB: recommended) or .DOC (571 kB) file for printing this work.
RESUMEN DIVULGATORIO Y PARA ESTUDIANTES EN CASTELLANO
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro el resumen en castellano en versión .PDF (204 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (96 kB)
“ANTAGONISMO ENTRE CIENCIAS DURAS Y HUMANIDADES BLANDAS”
MALFORMACIONES Y PAPEL DEL ÓRGANO CEREBRAL
Christofredo Jakob: “Los Monstruos Anencéfalos” (Spanish)
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (346 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (280 kB).
BIOÉTICA
Éthique de la Bio-Éthique (français) ¡Nuevo!
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (323 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (161 kB).
EL PRESUNTO DUALISMO CUERPO - ALMA
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (373 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (201 kB)
PSICOANÁLISIS Y FACILITACIóN PSICOSOMÁTICA DE LA ENF. DE ALZHEIMER
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (502 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (110 kB)
PERICIAS JUDICIALES Y CASUÍSTICA
Puede leer, imprimir o guardar en su disco duro esta investigación en versión .PDF (300 kB: recomendada) o .DOC (150 kB)
NUESTRA GENTE
Reseña biográfica: Ramón Carrillo, el Gran Sanitarista Argentino (Spanish)